Skip to main content
Log in

Dominance in spatial voting with imprecise ideals

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We introduce a dominance relationship in spatial voting with Euclidean preferences, by treating voter ideal points as balls of radius \(\delta\). Values \(\delta >0\) model imprecision or ambiguity as to voter preferences from the perspective of a social planner. The winning coalitions may be any consistent monotonic collection of voter subsets. We characterize the minimum value of \(\delta\) for which the \(\delta\)-core, the set of undominated points, is nonempty. In the case of simple majority voting, the core is the yolk center and \(\delta\) is the yolk radius.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Place \(n-1\) ideal points at the vertices of a regular \((n-1)\)-polygon, and place the nth ideal point at the polygon center. Then for any small perturbation of the points, the nth point remains undominated.

  2. Stricly speaking, the yolk is not a solution concept since it was built as a tool to enclose the uncovered set. However, following Owen (Owen 1990), we interpret the yolk as a near-core concept.

References

  • Austen-Smith D (1996) Refinements of the heart. In: Collective decision-making: social choice and political economy, pages 221–236. Springer

  • Banks JS (1995) Singularity theory and core existence in the spatial model. J Math Econ 24:523–536

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banks JS, Duggan J, Le Breton M (2006) Social choice and electoral competition in the general spatial model. J Econ Theory 126:194–234

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger M (1978) Géométrie, vol 3 : Convexes et polytopes, polyèdres réguliers, aires et volumes. Fernand-Nathan, Paris

  • Borcherding K, Eppel T, Von Winterfeldt D (1991) Comparison of weighting judgments in multiattribute utility measurement. Manag Sci 37(12):1603–1619

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bräuninger T (2007) Stability in spatial voting games with restricted preference maximizing. J Theoretical Politics 19:173–191

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis OA, DeGroot MH, Hinich MJ (1972) Social preference orderings and majority rule. Econometrica 40:147–157

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eban G, Stephen WS (1990) Predicting committee behavior in majority rule voting experiments. RAND J Econ 21:293–313

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eisenführ F, Weber M, Langer T (2009) Rational decision making. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferejohn JA, McKelvey R, Packel E (1984) Limiting distributions for continuous state Markov models. Soc Choice Welf 1:45–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grandmont JM (1978) Intermediate preferences and the majority rule. Econometrica 46:317–330

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg J (1979) Consistent majority rules over compact sets of alternatives. Econometrica 47:627–636

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kramer GH (1977) A dynamical model of political equilibrium. J Econ Theory 16:310–334

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin M, Nganmeni Z (2016) Tovey craig a on the uniqueness of the yolk. Soc Choice Welf 47:511–518

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey RD (1986) Covering, dominance, and institution free properties of social choice. Am J Political Sci 30:283–314

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey RD, Tovey CA (2010) Approximating the yolk by the LP yolk. Math Soc Sci 1:102–109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller NR (1980) A new solution set for tournaments and majority voting. Am J Political Sci 24:68–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller NR (2015) The spatial model of social choice and voting. In: Heckelman JC, Miller NR (eds) Handbook of social choice and voting, chapter 10. Edward Elagar, Cheltenham, pp 163–181

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nakamura K (1979) The vetoers in a simple game with ordinal preferences. Int J Game Theory 8:55–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Owen G (1990) Stable outcomes in spatial voting games. Math Soc Sci 19:269–279

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plott C (1967) A notion of equilibrium and its possibility under majority rule. Am Econ Rev 57:787–806

    Google Scholar 

  • Rockafellar RT (1970) Convex analysis. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein A (1979) A note about the ‘nowhere denseness’ of societies having an equilibrium under majority rule. Econometrica 47:511–514

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saari DG (2014) Unifying voting theory from Nakamura’s to Greenberg’s theorems. Math Soc Sci 69:1–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schofield N (1983) Generic instability of majority rule. Rev Econ Stud 50:695–705

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schofield N (1995) Coalition politics: a formal model and empirical analysis. J Theoretical Politics 7:245–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schofield N, Tovey C (1992) A Probability and convergence for supra-majority rule with euclidean preferences. Math Comput Modell 16(8–9):41–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Serra J (2009) Uncertain Ideal Points and the Impact of Electoral Dimensions on the Vote Choice. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association 67th Annual National Conference, The Palmer House Hilton, Chicago, IL,

  • Shubik M, Wooders MH (1983) Approximate cores of replica games and economies Part II: set-up costs and firm formation in coalition production economies. Math Soc Sci 6:285–306

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steuer R (1976) E Multiple objective linear programming with interval criterion weights. Manag Sci 23(3):305–316

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tovey C. A (1991) Some foundations for empirical study in spatial euclidean social choice models. In W. Barnett, editor, Political Economy: Institutions, Competition, and Representation, chapter 7. Cambridge University Press, . presented at the Seventh International Symposium in Economic Theory and Econometrics

  • Tovey CA (2010) The instability of instability of centered distributions. Math Soc Sci 59:53–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tovey CA (2010) The probability of majority rule instability in the 2d euclidean model with an even snumber of voters. Soc Choice Welf 35:705–708

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber M, Borcherding K (1993) Behavioral influences on weight judgments in multiattribute decision making. Euro J Oper Res 67(1):1–12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wuffle A, Feld SL, Owen G, Grofman B (1989) Finagle’s law and the Finagle point: A new solution concept for two-candidate competition in spatial voting games without a core. Am J Political Sci 33:348–375

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mathieu Martin.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This research has been developed within the center of excellence MME-DII (ANR-11-LBX-0023-01).

Research supported by National Science Foundation Grant # 1335301.

Appendices

Appendix

1.1 A- Proofs

Throughout this section, \(\left( N,W,\{q^{i}\}_{i\in N},\delta \right) \equiv \left( V,\delta \right)\) is a \(m-\)dimensional spatial voting game where \(B(q^{i},\delta )\) is the imprecise ideals locale of the voter \(i\in N\).

1.1.1 Proof of Proposition 1

Suppose y is \(\delta\)-dominated by some point z with respect to a coalition \(T\in W\). Let \(\mathcal {H}=\{x:||x-z||=||x-y||\}\) be the hyperplane orthogonal to and bisecting segment \(\left[ y,z\right]\), Fig. 5a. Let \(\mathcal {H}^{z}\) (respectively \(\mathcal {H}^{y}\)) be the open halfspace defined by \(\mathcal {H}\) that contains z (respectively y). By definition of \(\delta\)-dominance, \(\forall i\in T,\) \(B(q^{i},\delta )\subset \mathcal {H}^{z}\). Hence the set \(\mathcal {S}\equiv \bigcup _{i\in T} B(q^{i},\delta )\subset \mathcal {H}^{z}\). Since \(\mathcal {H}^{z}\) is convex, the convex hull \(Conv(T,\delta )\subset \mathcal {H}^{z}\) as well. Then \(y\in \mathcal {H}^{y}\Rightarrow y\not \in \mathcal {H}^{z}\Rightarrow y\not \in Conv(T,\delta )\).

Conversely, suppose \(y\not \in Conv(T,\delta )\). The set \(\mathcal {S}\) is a finite union of compact sets and therefore is compact. It is known from Caratheodory’s Theorem (see e.g. Theorem  11.1.8.6 in (Berger 1978)) that in \(\mathbb {R} ^{m}\) the convex hull of any compact set is compact. Hence the convex hull \(Conv(T,\delta )\) is compact. By (Rockafellar 1970, Corollary 11.4.2 p. 99), there exists a hyperplane \(\Pi =\{x:\pi \cdot x=\pi _{0}\}\) strictly separating \(\left\{ y\right\}\) from \(Conv(T,\delta )\), such that \(\pi \cdot y<\pi _{0}\) and \(\pi \cdot x>\pi _{0},\ \forall x\in Conv(T,\delta )\), Fig. 5-(b).

Let p be the projection of y onto \(\Pi\), so \(\pi \cdot p=\pi _{0}\) and \(p=y+\alpha \pi\) for some scalar \(\alpha >0\).

Fig. 5
figure 5

\(\delta\)-dominated positions

Geometrically one can see that p is closer than y to every point in \(Conv(T,\delta )\) because \(p\in \Pi\) and y is on the other side of \(\Pi\) from \(Conv(T,\delta )\). Algebraically, for all \(x\in Conv(T,\delta )\),

$$\begin{aligned} ||p-x||^{2}&=(p-x)\cdot (y+\alpha \pi -x)\\&=\alpha \pi \cdot p-\alpha \pi \cdot x+p\cdot y+||x||^{2}-x\cdot p-x\cdot y\\&<\alpha \pi _{0}-\alpha \pi _{0}+p\cdot y+||x||^{2}-x\cdot p-x\cdot y\\&<\alpha \pi \cdot x-\alpha \pi \cdot y+p\cdot y+||x||^{2}-x\cdot p-x\cdot y\\&=(x-y)\cdot (x+\alpha \pi -p)=||y-x||^{2}. \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, p \(\delta\)-dominates y with respect to coalition T, which completes the proof. \(\square\)

1.1.2 Proof of Corollary 1

The proof of the Corollary follows immediately from Proposition 1 and the definition of \(\delta\)-core. \(\square\)

1.1.3 Proof of Corollary 2

Consider the function \(\rho\) defined from \(\mathbb {R} ^{m}\) to \(\mathbb {R}\) by: \(\forall z\in \mathbb {R} ^{m}\), \(\rho (z)=\underset{S\in W}{\max }\) \(d\left( z,Conv(S)\right)\). Finding a minimum for the function \(\rho\) may be restricted to \(Conv\left( N \right)\), the convex hull of \(\left\{ q^{i}\right\} _{i\in N}\). Indeed, if \(z\notin Conv\left( N\right)\), then there is a point l such that for all \(S\in W,\) \(d\left( l,Conv(S)\right) <d\left( z,Conv(S)\right)\). However for all \(S\in W\), \(d\left( l,Conv(S)\right) <d\left( z,Conv(S)\right)\) implies that \(\underset{S\in W}{\max }\) \(d\left( l,Conv(S)\right) <\underset{S\in W}{\max }\) \(d\left( z,Conv(S)\right) ,\) i.e. \(\rho (l)<\rho (z).\)

The function \(\rho\) is continuous as it is the maximum of finitely many continuous functions. By Caratheodory’s Theorem \(Conv\left( N\right)\) is compact. It follows that \(\rho\) attains its minimum at a point \(z^{*}\). Let \(\delta ^{*}=\rho (z^{*})=\underset{Z}{\min }\left( \underset{S}{\max }\text { }d\left( z,Conv(S)\right) \right)\). By definition, \(\delta ^{*}\) coincides with r the radius of a g-yolk.

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{lll} Moreover, \delta ^{*}=\rho (z^{*})=\underset{S\in W}{\max } d\left( z^{*},Conv(S)\right) &{} \iff &{} \forall S\in W, d\left( z^{*},Conv(S)\right) \le \delta ^{*}\\ &{} \iff &{} \forall S\in W, z^{*}\in Conv(S,\delta ^{*})\\ &{} \iff &{} z^{*}\in \underset{S\in W}{\cap }Conv(S,\delta ^{*} )=C(V,\delta ^{*}) \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
(1)

Therefore, \(C(V,\delta ^{*})\ne \varnothing\). Furthermore, if \(\delta \ge \delta ^{*}\) then \(C(V,\delta ^{*})\subseteq C\left( V,\delta \right)\) i.e. \(C\left( V,\delta \right) \ne \varnothing\).

Now, for a \(\delta \ge 0,\) assume that \(C\left( V,\delta \right) \ne \varnothing .\) Then there exists \(x\in C\left( V,\delta \right) =\underset{S\in W}{\cap }Conv(S,\delta )\), such that for all \(S\in W,\) \(d\left( x,Conv(S)\right) \le \delta .\) It follows that \(\rho \left( x\right) =\underset{S\in W}{\max }\) \(d\left( x,Conv(S)\right) \le \delta\). We already know that \(\delta ^{*}\le \rho \left( x\right)\). Then \(\delta ^{*} \le \delta\) i.e. \(C\left( V,\delta \right) \ne \varnothing \Rightarrow \delta \ge \delta ^{*}\). \(\blacksquare\)

1.1.4 Proof of Corollary 3

According to the proof of Corollary 2, \(z\in C\left( V,\delta ^{*}\right) =C\left( V,r\right)\), where r is the radius of a g-yolk if and only if for all \(S\in W,\) \(B\left( z,r\right) \cap Conv(S)\ne \varnothing\). The radius r of all g-yolks is unique since it is minimal. If there is a unique center c such that B(cr) is a g-yolk, then by definition the \(\delta -core\) is the singleton c. \(\blacksquare\)

B- an example

In this example, we find the center C and radius r of the g-yolk depend on the set of winning coalitions. For \(q^{1}=(1,3);\) \(q^{2}=(2,0);\) \(q^{3}=(0,2);\) \(q^{4}=(2,2)\) and \(q^{5}=O=(0,0),\) we show that : \(\left( i\right)\) for simple majority voting \(c=(1,\frac{1+\sqrt{5}}{2})\) and \(r=\frac{\sqrt{10}-\sqrt{2}}{4}\); \(\left( ii\right)\) for weighted voting game \(V=\left[ 51;6,40,77,40\right]\), \(c=(1,\frac{\sqrt{10}-1}{3})\) and \(r=\frac{\sqrt{10}-1}{3}\) and \(\left( iii\right)\) for weighted voting game \(V=\left[ 54;6,40,77,40\right]\), \(c=(1,r)\) and \(r=\sqrt{2}-1\). Figures 4(i), (ii), iii) provided earlier in Sect. 3.3 relate to this example.

\(\left( i\right)\) Let \(F=(0.5,1.5)=\left( q^{1}q^{5}\right) \cap \left( q^{2}q^{3}\right)\). The radius of the inscribed circle of triangle \(q^{1}q^{2}F\) is the ratio of its area to semiperimeter. A unitary orientation vector of the line \(\left( q^{1}q^{2}\right)\) is \(\frac{\overrightarrow{q^{1}q^{2}}}{\left\| \overrightarrow{q^{1}q^{2}}\right\| }=\left( \frac{1}{\sqrt{10}},-\frac{3}{\sqrt{10}}\right)\). A normal vector of \(\left( q^{1}q^{2}\right)\) is \(\overrightarrow{u}=\left( \frac{3}{\sqrt{10}},\frac{1}{\sqrt{10}}\right)\). Line \(\left( q^{1}q^{2}\right)\) is the set of points \(p=(x_{1},x_{2})\) that check the normalized equation \(\overrightarrow{u}\cdot \overrightarrow{q^{2}p}=0\) i.e. \(\overrightarrow{u}\cdot \overrightarrow{Op}=\overrightarrow{u}\cdot \overrightarrow{Oq^{2}}\). It follows that \(\left( \frac{3}{\sqrt{10}},\frac{1}{\sqrt{10}}\right) \cdot (x_{1},x_{2})=\frac{6}{\sqrt{10}}\). The distance from F to \(\left( q^{1}q^{2}\right)\) is therefore \(\frac{6}{\sqrt{10}}-\overrightarrow{u} \cdot \overrightarrow{OF}=(\frac{1}{\sqrt{10}})\left( 6-(1.5+1.5)\right) =\frac{3}{\sqrt{10}}\). Therefore the area of the triangle \(q^{1}q^{2}F\) is \(\frac{1}{2}(\frac{3}{\sqrt{10}})\overline{q^{1}q^{2}}=\frac{3}{2}\). Its semiperimeter is \(\frac{1}{2}(\sqrt{10}+\frac{3}{2}\sqrt{2}+\frac{1}{2} \sqrt{10})\) \(=\frac{3}{4}(\sqrt{10}+\sqrt{2})\). The radius is \(r=\frac{2}{\sqrt{10}+\sqrt{2}}=\frac{1}{4}(\sqrt{10}-\sqrt{2})\).

The normalized equation for \(\left( q^{2}q^{3}\right)\) is \(\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}(x_{1}+x_{2})=\sqrt{2}\). The \(c_{1}\) coordinate of the yolk center is 1, by symmetry. Let the yolk center have coordinates \((1,c_{2})\). It must satisfy \(\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}(1+c_{2})=\sqrt{2}+r\). Hence \(\frac{\sqrt{2}}{2}+c_{2}\frac{\sqrt{2}}{2}=\sqrt{2}+\frac{\sqrt{10}}{4}-\frac{\sqrt{2}}{4}\) \(\Rightarrow c_{2}=\sqrt{2}\left( \frac{\sqrt{2}}{4}+\frac{\sqrt{10}}{4}\right) =\frac{1+\sqrt{5}}{2}\).

To summarize, the yolk’s center is \(c=(1,\frac{1+\sqrt{5}}{2})\) and its radius is \(r=\frac{\sqrt{10}-\sqrt{2}}{4}\). It also must be verified that this circle intersects the median line defined by the segment \(\left[ q^{3},q^{4}\right]\). We require \(\frac{1+\sqrt{5}}{2}+r\ge 2\). The calculation is \(\frac{1}{4}(2+2\sqrt{5}+\sqrt{10}-\sqrt{2})\approx \frac{8.21}{4}>2\).

\(\left( ii\right)\) For the weighted voting case with threshold 51 the minimal coalitions are \(\left\{ 2,5\right\}\), \(\left\{ 1,3,5\right\}\), \(\left\{ 1,2,4\right\}\), and also \(\left\{ 3,4,5\right\}\) and \(\left\{ 2,3,4\right\}\). The first three are met by the inscribed circle of triangle \(q^{1}q^{2}q^{5}\). The triangle’s area is \(\frac{1}{2}(2)(3)=3\). Its semiperimeter is \(\frac{1}{2}\left( \sqrt{10}+\sqrt{10}+2\right) =\sqrt{10}+1\). The radius is therefore \(r=\frac{3}{\sqrt{10}+1}=\frac{\sqrt{10} -1}{3}\). The center has coordinates \((1,\frac{\sqrt{10}-1}{3})\) because the circle is tangent to the convex combinations of the winning coalition \(\left\{ 2,5\right\}\).

\(\left( iii\right)\) For the weighted voting case with threshold 54, voter 1 is not a member of any minimal winning coalition. Those coalitions are \(\left\{ 2,5\right\}\), \(\left\{ 3,4,5\right\}\), and \(\left\{ 2,3,4\right\}\). The yolk is the inscribed circle of the triangle with vertices \(q^{2}\), \(q^{5}\), and \(\left( q^{2}q^{3}\right) \cap \left( q^{4}q^{5}\right) =(1,1)\). The triangle area is 1 since it is \(\frac{1}{4}\) of \(2^{2}\) by symmetry of the square \(q^{3}q^{4}q^{2}q^{5}\). The semiperimeter is \(\frac{1}{2}(2+2\sqrt{2})=\sqrt{2}+1\). The radius is therefore \(r=\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}+1}=\sqrt{2}-1\). As in the previous case, the circle must be tangent to \(\left( q^{2}q^{5}\right)\), so its center is \((1,\sqrt{2}-1)\). \(\blacksquare\)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Martin, M., Nganmeni, Z. & Tovey, C.A. Dominance in spatial voting with imprecise ideals. Soc Choice Welf 57, 181–195 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-021-01316-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-021-01316-z

Navigation