Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Holdings about holdings: modeling contradictions in judicial precedent

  • Published:
Artificial Intelligence and Law Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper attempts to formalize the differences between two methods of analysis used by judicial opinions in common law jurisdictions to contradict holdings posited by earlier opinions: “disagreeing” with the holdings of the earlier opinions and “attributing” holdings to the prior opinions. The paper will demonstrate that it is necessary to model both methods of analysis differently to generate an accurate picture of the state of legal authority in hypothetical examples, as well as in an example based on Barry Friedman’s analysis of the “stealth overruling” of Miranda v. Arizona through subsequent judicial interpretations. Because the question of whether “disagreement” and “attribution” need to be modeled separately relates to contradictions rather than to subtler interactions between holdings such as “distinguishing,” it can be answered using the simple technique of modeling holdings as propositional variables and evaluating the holdings using truth tables.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In effect, because no truth value is deemed to contradict “Undecided,” lower courts in this model are not barred from deciding issues that have been left expressly undecided by higher courts.

  2. As a mnemonic device, note that the abbreviations are ordered alphabetically from the strongest level of authority to the weakest.

  3. That is to say, “(x → y) → ((z → ¬x) → (z → ¬y))” is not valid because it is falsifiable where x is false but y and z are true.

References

  • Alexander L (2012) Precedential constraint, its scope and strength: a brief survey of the possibilities and their merits. In: Bustamante T, Bernal C (eds) On the philosophy of precedent. Franz Steiner Verlag, Stuttgart, pp 75–82

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashley KD, Rissland EL (1987) But, see, accord: generating blue book citations in hypo. In: Proceedings of the first international conference on artificial intelligence and law. ACM Press, New York, pp 67–74

  • Bench-Capon TJM, Coenen F (1992) Isomorphism and legal knowledge based systems. Artif Intell Law 1:65–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benesh SC, Reddick M (2002) Overruled: an event history analysis of lower court reaction to Supreme Court alteration of precedent. J Polit 64(2):534–550

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berman DH, Hafner CD (1991) Incorporating procedural context into a model of case-based legal reasoning. In: Proceedings of the third international conference on artificial intelligence and law. ACM Press, New York, pp 12–20

  • Berman DH, Hafner CD (1995) Understanding precedents in a temporal context of evolving legal doctrine. In: Proceedings of the fifth international conference on artificial intelligence and law. ACM Press, New York, pp 42–51

  • Bloom H (2003) A map of misreading: with a new preface. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Branting LK (1991) Reasoning with portions of precedents. In: Proceedings of the third international conference on artificial intelligence and law. ACM Press, New York, pp 145–154

  • Branting LK (1994) A computational model of ratio decidendi. Artif Intell Law 2:1–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carey M (2011) Modeling authority commitments in two search and seizure cases. In: Proceedings of the thirteenth international conference on artificial intelligence and law. ACM Press, New York, pp 181–188

  • Dworkin R (1986) Law’s empire. Belknap Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman B (2010) The wages of stealth overruling (with particular attention to Miranda v. Arizona). Georget Law J 99:1–63

    Google Scholar 

  • Hage JC, Leenes R, Lodder AR (1994) Hard cases: a procedural approach. Artif Intell Law 2:113–167

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1958) Positivism and the separation of law and morals. Harv Law Rev 71:593–629

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horty JF (2011) Rules and reasons in the theory of precedent. Leg Theory 17:1–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horty JF, Bench-Capon TJM (2012) A factor-based definition of precedential constraint. Artif Intell Law 20:181–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kannan PM (1993) The precedential force of panel law. Marquette L Rev 76:755–766

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz D (2006) Institutional rules, strategic behavior, and the legacy of Chief Justice William Rehnquist: setting the record straight on Dickerson v. United States. J Law Politics 22:303–340

    Google Scholar 

  • Leach WB (1967) Revisionism in the House of Lords: the bastion of rigid stare decisis falls. Harv L Rev 80:797–803

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leval PN (2006) Judging under the constitution: dicta about dicta. N Y Univ Law Rev 81:1249–1282

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarty LT (1995) An implementation of Eisner v. Macomber. In: Proceedings of the fifth international conference on artificial intelligence and law. ACM Press, New York, pp 276–286

  • McClurg SD, Comparato SA (2003) Rebellious or just misunderstood? Assessing measures of lower court compliance with Supreme Court precedent. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association, Philadelphia

  • Raz J (2009) The authority of law: essays on law and morality: second edition. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Stinson JM (2010) Why dicta becomes holding and why it matters. Brooklyn Law Rev 76:219–264

    Google Scholar 

  • Todd J (2007) Undead precedent: the curse of a holding limited to its facts. Tex Tech Law Rev 40:67–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining W, Miers D (2010) How to do things with rules: fifth edition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (1994) Vagueness in law and language: some philosophical issues. Calif Law Rev 82:509–540

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wyner A, Bench-Capon TJM (2007) Argument schemes for legal case-based reasoning. In: Lodder AR, Mommers L (eds) Legal knowledge and information systems, JURIX 2007. IOS Press, Amsterdam, pp 139–149

    Google Scholar 

  • Wyner A, Bench-Capon TJM (2009) Modelling judicial context in argumentation frameworks. J Log Comput 19:941–968

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Michael Poulshock and John Horty for their helpful comments and suggestions about this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew Carey.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Carey, M. Holdings about holdings: modeling contradictions in judicial precedent. Artif Intell Law 21, 341–365 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10506-013-9141-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10506-013-9141-3

Keywords

Navigation