Skip to main content
Log in

A Formal Characterisation of Hamblin’s Action-State Semantics

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Hamblin’s Action-State Semantics provides a sound philosophical foundation for understanding the character of the imperative. Taking this as our inspiration, in this paper we present a logic of action, which we call ST, that captures the clear ontological distinction between being responsible for the achievement of a state of affairs and being responsible for the performance of an action. We argue that a relativised modal logic of type RT founded upon a ternary relation over possible worlds integrated with a basic tense logic captures intuitions of the Hamblinian model of imperatives. The logic implements a direct mapping of each of Hamblin’s key concepts: strategies, partial strategies and wholehearted satisfaction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Åqvist, L.: 1975, A New Approach to the Logical Theory of Interrogatives, TBL Verlag Gunter Barr, Tubingen, Germany.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, R. J.: 1976, Agreeing to disagree, Annals of Statistics 4(6), 1236–1239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.: 1962, How to do Things with Words, Oxford University Press, London, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barringer, H., Fisher, M., Gabbay, D., Gough, G., and Owens, R.: 1995, MetateM: an introduction, Formal Aspects of Computing 7(5), 533–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N. and Perloff, M.: 1988, Seeing to it that: A canonical form for agentives, Theroria 9, 175–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N. and Perloff, M.: 1992, The way of the agent, Studia Logica 51(3/4), 463–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N., Perloff, M., and Xu, M.: 2001, Facing the Future, Oxford University Press, London, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P., de Rijke, M., and Venema, Y.: 2001, Modal Logic, Vol. 53 of Cambridge Tracts in Theoretical Computer Science, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blum, A. L. and Furst, M. L.: 1997, Fast planning through planning graph analysis, Artificial Intelligence 90(1,2), 279–298.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowen, K. A.: 1979, Model Theory for Modal Logic, Reidel, Amsterdam, The Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chellas, B. F.: 1980, Modal Logic: An Introduction, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chellas, B. F.: 1992, Time and modality in the logic of agency, Studia Logica 51(3/4), 485–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • d’Altan, P., Meyer, J.-J. C., and Wieringa, R. J.: 1996, An integrated framework for ought-to-be and ought-to-do constraints, Artificial Intelligence and Law 4(2), 77–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D.: 2001, Essays on Actions and Events, 2nd edn, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dignum, F. and Meyer, J.-J. C.: 1990, Negations of transactions and their use in the specification of dynamic and deontic integrity constraints, in M. Kwiatkowska, M. W. Shields, and R. M. Thomas (eds.), Semantics for Concurrency, Springer, Berlin Heidelberg New York, pp. 61–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgesem, D.: 1997, The modal logic of agency, Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic 2(2), 1–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fagin, R., Halpern, J. Y., Moses, Y., and Vardi, M. Y.: 1995, Reasoning about Knowledge, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feys, R.: 1965, Modal Logics, Louvain, E. Nauwelaerts.

  • Fikes, R. E. and Nilsson, N. J.: 1971, STRIPS: a new approach to the application of theorem proving to problem solving, Artificial Intelligence 2, 189–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, M., Howey, R., and Long, D. P.: 2005, Validating plans in the context of processes and exogenous events, in Proceedings of the Twentieth National Conference on Artificial Intelligence, pp. 1151–1156.

  • Giunchiglia, F., Lee, J., Lifschitz, V., McCain, N., and Turner, H.: 2004, Nonmonotonic causal theories, Artificial Intelligence 153(1,2), 49–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goranko, V. and Zanardo, A.: 2004, Combining linear orders with modalities for possible histories, in W. A. Carnielli, F. M. Dionísio, and P. Mateus (eds.), The Workshop on Combination of Logics: Theory and Applications (CombLog 04), Vol. 4(5). http://www.cle.unicamp.br/e-prints/vol_4,n_5,2004.html, CLE e-Prints.

  • Hamblin, C. L.: 1987, Imperatives, Blackwell, Oxford, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J., Halonen, I., and Mutanen, A.: 2000, Interrogative logic as a general theory of reasoning, in R. H. Johnson and J. Woods (eds.), Handbook of Practical Reasoning, Kluwer, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. F.: 2001, Agency and Deontic Logic, Oxford University Press, London, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. F. and N. Belnap: 1995, The deliberative stit: A study of action, omission, ability, and obligation, Journal of Philosophical Logic 24, 583–644.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G. E. and Cresswell, M. J.: 1996, A New Introduction to Modal Logic, Routledge, London, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, A. I. J. and Sergot, M. J.: 1996, A formal characterisation of institutionalised power, Journal of the IGPL 4(3), 429–445.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kowalski, R. A. and Sergot, M. J.: 1986, A logic-based calculus of events, New Generation Computing 4, 67–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lemmon, E. J.: 1957, New foundations for Lewis modal systems, Journal of Symbolic Logic 22, 176–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levesque, H. J., Reiter, R., Lesperance, Y., Lin, F., and Scherl, R. B.: 1997,GOLOG: A logic programming language for dynamic domains, Journal of Logic Programming 31, 59–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macleod, M. C. and Schotch, P. K.: 2000, Remarks on the modal logic of Henry Bradford Smith, Journal of Philosophical Logic 29, 603–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, J. and Hayes, P.: 1969, Some philosophical problems from the standpoint of artificial intelligence, in D. Michie and B. Meltzer (eds.), Machine Intelligence, Vol. 4, Edinburgh University Press, pp. 463–502.

  • Migita, T. and Hosoi, T.: 1997, Gentzen-types formulation of some modal logics, SUT Journal of Mathematics 33(2), 207–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norman, T. J. and Reed, C. A.: 2002, Group delegation and responsibility, in Proceedings of the First International Joint Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multi-Agent Systems, pp. 491–498.

  • Pirri, F. and Reiter, R.: 1999, Some contributions to the metatheory of the situation calculus, Journal of the ACM 46(3), 325–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A.: 1967, Past, Present and Future, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santos, F., Jones, A. J. I., and Carmo, J.: 1997, Responsibility for action in organisations: a formal model, in G. Holmström-Hintikka and R. Tuomela (eds.), Contemporary Action Theory, Vol. 2, Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp. 333–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R.: 1969, Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segerberg, K.: 1989, Bringing it about, Journal of Philosophical Logic 18, 327–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer, G., Gillet, P. R., and Sckerl, R.: 2000, The logic of events, Annals of Mathematics and AI 28(1–4), 315–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanahan, M.: 1997, Solving the Frame Problem: A Mathematical Investigation of the Common Sense Law of Inertia, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh, M. P.: 1991, Towards a formal theory of communication for multi-agent systems, in Proceedings of the Twelth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, pp. 69–74.

  • Singh, M. P.: 1993, A semantics for speech acts, Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 8, 47–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomason, R. H.: 1984, Combinations of tense and modality, in D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Vol. II, Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 135–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G. H.: 1968, An essay in deontic logic and the general theory of action, Vol. 21 of Acta Philosophica Fennica, North-Holland, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. and Krabbe, E. C. W.: 1995, Commitment in Dialogue: Basic Concepts of Interpersonal Reasoning, SUNY, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Xu, M.: 1995, On the basic logic of STIT with a single agent, Journal of Symbolic Logic 60(2), 459–483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Timothy J. Norman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Reed, C., Norman, T.J. A Formal Characterisation of Hamblin’s Action-State Semantics. J Philos Logic 36, 415–448 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-006-9041-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-006-9041-z

Key words

Navigation