Skip to main content
Log in

Holism, Meaning Similarity and Inferential Space—a Measurement Theoretic Approach

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Proponents of meaning holism often invoke notions of meaning similarity and semantic spatiality in order to counter accusations that holism renders language unstable and chaotic. However, talk of such notions often falls short of being explicit and formal. In this paper I present an algebraically couched theory of inferential similarity and spatiality, motivated by measurement theory, and I apply it to the discussion of meaning holism. I argue that the proposed theory offers new and improved conceptual resources for facing the challenges raised against the thesis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Block, N. (1986). Advertisement for a semantics for psychology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10, 615–678.

  2. Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Cambridge: Harvard.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Brandom, R. (2007). Inferentialism and some of its challenges. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74, 651–676.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Churchland, P.M. (1993). State space semantics and meaning holism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 3, 667–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Churchland, P. (1979). Scientific realism and the plasticity of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  6. Churchland, P.M. (1998). Conceptual similarity across sensory and neural diversity: the Fodor/Lepore challenge answered. Journal of Philosophy, 95, 5–32.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Davidson, D. (1984). Radical interpretation. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Inquiries into truth and interpretation (pp. 125–139). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  8. Davidson, D. (2004). The problem of objectivity. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Problems of rationality (pp. 125–139). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  9. Díez, J.A. (1997). A hundred years of numbers: an historical introduction to measurement theory 1887-1990. Part I: the formation period. Two lines of research: axiomatics and real morphisms, scales and invariance. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 28, 167–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Dresner, E. (2002). Holism, language acquisition and algebraic logic. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25, 419–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Dresner, E. (2004). Over-assignment of structure. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 33, 467–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Dresner, E. (2006). A measurement theoretic account of propositions. Synthese, 153, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Dresner, E. (2010). Language and the measure of mind. Mind and Language, 25, 418–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Dresner, E. (2014). Decision theory, propositional measurement, and unified interpretation. Mind, 123, 707–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Fodor, J., & Lepore, E. (1992). Holism: a shopper’s guide. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Fodor, J., & Lepore, E. (1999). All at sea in semantic space: Churchland on meaning similarity. Journal of Philosophy, 96, 381–403.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Jackman, H. (1999). Moderate holism and the instability thesis. American Philosophical Quarterly, 36, 361–9.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Jonsson (2014). Semantic holism and language learning. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 43, 725–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Krantz, D., Luce, D., Suppes, P., Tversky, A. (1971). Foundations of measurement (Vol. 1–3). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Matthews, R. (2007). The measure of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  21. Pagin, P. (1997). Is compositionality compatible with holism? Mind & Language, 12, 11–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Pagin, P. (2006). In E. Lepore, & B. Smith (Eds.), Meaning holism, (pp. 213-232). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  23. Quine, W.V. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review, 60, 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Quine, W.V. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Sagi, G. (2014). Formality in logic: from logical terms to semantic constraints. Logique et Analyse, 227, 259–276.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Sellars, W. (1953). Inference and meaning. Mind, 62, 313–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Shapiro, S. (2006). Vagueness in context. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  28. Swoyer, C. (1991). Structural representation and surrogative reasoning. Synthese, 87, 449–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Tiffany, E. (1999). Semantics San Diego style. Journal of Philosophy, 96, 416–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. van Benthem, J. (1994). Modal foundations for Predicate Logic. Report No. CSLI-94-191. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Warfield, T. (1993). On a semantic argument against conceptual role semantics. Analysis, 53, 298–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Eliran Haziza for his comments and help, and also to the anonymous reviewers of the Journal of Philosophical Logic. This research was supported by the Israeli Science Foundation (Grant No. 610/2016).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eli Dresner.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dresner, E. Holism, Meaning Similarity and Inferential Space—a Measurement Theoretic Approach. J Philos Logic 48, 611–630 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-018-9487-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-018-9487-9

Keywords

Navigation