Abstract
Kripke (Wittgenstein on rules and private language: an elementary exposition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Mass, 1982) rejected a naturalistic dispositional account of meaning (hereafter semantic dispositionalism) in a skeptical argument about rule-following he attributes to Wittgenstein (Philosophical investigation. Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1958). Most philosophers who oppose Kripke’s criticisms of semantic dispositionalism take the stance that the argument proves too much: semantic dispositionalism is similar to much of our respected science in some important aspects, and hence to discard the former would mean to give up the latter, which is obviously wrong. In this paper, I shall discuss and reject a recent defense of Kripke by Kusch (Analysis 65(2):156–163 2005; Sceptical guide to meaning and rules: defending Kripke’s Wittgenstein. McGill-Queen’s, London, 2006). Kusch attempts to show that semantic dispositionalism differs from the sciences, and consequently, Kripke’s attack can only target semantic dispositionalism, but not the sciences. Specifically, Kusch identifies some important features of the sciences with regard to how it employs idealization and ceteris paribus clauses, and argues that the ways in which semantic dispositionalism uses them are dramatically different. I argue that, upon close examination, the two are more similar than otherwise in each of those features.
Similar content being viewed by others
Explore related subjects
Discover the latest articles, news and stories from top researchers in related subjects.Notes
Note that Boghossian and Pettit differ in their views on the prospects of semantic dispositionalism. Boghossian holds that semantic dispositionalism is hopeless because it fails to meet the Normativity Objection, whereas Pettit tries to develop sophisticated versions of dispositionalism which can deal with this objection by specifying a suitable set of normality conditions.
Kusch’s discussion on the problem of semantic dispositionalism in meeting the Finite Objection is largely the same in the 2005 paper and 2006 book. In what follows, we concentrate our discussion on the 2005 version.
c.f. McMullin 1985.
This expression comes from Morreau (1999).
Morreau (1999: p. 172) has also made this remark.
See Pietroski and Rey (1995) for a similar discussion.
I borrow the ‘abstraction’ expression from Lin (1996), who not only distinguishes between the idealization and abstraction readings of cp-clauses, but also holds that to move from the former to the latter marks significant progress in natural sciences. Schurz (2002) also makes this distinction, calling them ‘exclusive’ and ‘comparative’ readings of cp, respectively, and further regards some versions of exclusive cp-laws as hopelessly vacuous.
References
Blackburn, S. (1984). The individualism strikes back. Synthese, 58, 281–301.
Boghossian, P. (1989). The rule-following considerations. Mind, 98, 281–301.
Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1991). You can fool some of the people all of the time, other things being equal: Hedged laws and psychological explanation. Mind, 100, 19–34.
Forbes, G. (1984). Scepticism and semantic knowledge. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 84, 223–237.
Hohwy, J. (2003). A reductio of Kripke-Wittgenstein’s objections to dispositionalism about meaning. Minds and Machines, 13, 257–268.
Inwagen, P. van. (1992). There is no such thing as addition. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 17, 138–159.
Joseph, G. (1980). The many sciences and the one world. Journal of Philosophy, 77, 773–790.
Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language: An elementary exposition. Cambridge Mass: Harvard University Press.
Kusch, M. (2005). Fodor v. Kripke: Semantic dispositionalism, idealization, and ceteris paribus clauses. Analysis, 65(2), 156–163. (April).
Kusch, M. (2006). A sceptical guide to meaning and rules: Defending Kripke’s Wittgenstein. London: McGill-Queen’s.
Lin, C. (1996). Idealization in scientific laws. Journal of National Institute for Compilation and Translation, 25, 197–305.
Lipton, P. (1999). All else being equal. Philosophy, 74, 155–168.
Martin, C. B., & Heil, J. (1998). Rules and powers. Philosophical Perspectives, 12, 283–312.
McManus, D. (2000). Boghossian, Miller, and Lewis on dispositional theories of meaning. Mind and Language, 15(4), 393–399.
McMullin, D. (1985). Galilean idealization. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 16, 247–273.
Morreau, M. (1999). Other things being equal. Philosophical Studies, 96, 163–182.
Mumford, S. (1998). Dispositions. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Pettit, P. (1996). The common mind: An essay on psychology, society, and politics (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pietroski, P., & Rey, G. (1995). When other things aren’t equal: Saving ceteris paribus laws from vacuity. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46, 81–110.
Schurz, G. (2002). Ceteris paribus laws: Classification and deconstruction. Erkenntnis, 57, 351–372.
Sober, E. (1984). The nature of selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical Investigation (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Acknowledgements
An earlier version was presented at Academia Sinica in Taipei, and I thank the audience for the feedback. I have also benefited from Martin Kusch′s helpful comments. I owe a special debt to Cheng-hung Lin who generously shares with me his insightful ideas in the past few years. The completion of this paper was made possible by the research grants I receive from the National Science Council of Taiwan (NSC 96-2411-H-194-009-MY3) and its Center for Humanities Research.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Cheng, KY. Semantic Dispositionalism, Idealization, and Ceteris Paribus Clauses. Minds & Machines 19, 407–419 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-009-9153-7
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-009-9153-7