Abstract
David Lewis famously proposed to model conventions as solutions to coordination games, where equilibrium selection is driven by precedence, or the history of play. A characteristic feature of Lewis Conventions is that they are intrinsically non-normative. Some philosophers have argued that for this reason they miss a crucial aspect of our folk notion of convention. It is doubtful however that Lewis was merely analysing a folk concept. I illustrate how his theory can (and must) be assessed using empirical data, and argue that it does indeed miss an important aspect of real-world conventions.
Similar content being viewed by others
References
Alexander J. M. (2007) The structural evolution of morality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Armel K. C., Beaumel A., Rangel A. (2008) Biasing simple choices by manipulating relative visual attention. Judgment and Decision Making 3: 396–403
Bacharach M. (2006) Beyond individual choice: Teams and frames in game theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Bardsley N. (2007) On collective intentions: Collective action in economics and philosophy. Synthese 157: 141–159
Bicchieri C. (2006) The grammar of society. Cambridge University Press, New York
Binmore K. (1994) Game theory and the social contract, Vol. 1: Playing fair. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA
Bratman M. (1993) Shared intention. Ethics 104: 97–113
Carrara M., Varzi A. C. (2001) Ontological commitment and reconstructivism. Erkenntnis 55: 33–50
Charness G., Rabin M. (2002) Understanding social preferences with simple tests. Quarterly Journal of Economics 117: 817–869
Crawford V. P., Gneezy U., Rottenstreich Y. (2008) The power of focal points is limited: Even minute payoff asymmetry may yield large coordination failures. American Economic Review 98: 1443–1458
Gilbert M. (1989) On social facts. Routledge, London
Gilbert M. (2008) Social convention revisited. Topoi 27: 5–16
Guala F. (2006) Has game theory been refuted?. Journal of Philosophy 103: 239–263
Guala, F., & Mittone, L. (2008). An experimental study of conventions and norms. CEEL working paper 8-10. University of Trento.
Guala F., Mittone L. (2010) How history and convention create norms: An experimental study. Journal of Economic Psychology 31: 749–756
Higgins E. T., Bargh J. A. (1987) Social cognition and social perception. Annual Review of Psychology 38: 369–425
Hodgson T., Guala F., Miller T., Summers I. (2012) Limbic and prefrontal activity during conformity and violation of norms in a coordination game. Journal of Neuroscience, Psychology, and Economics 5: 1–17
Horowitz T. (1998) Philosophical intuitions and psychological theory. In: DePaul M., Ramsey W. (eds) Rethinking intuition: The psychology of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry. Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham, MD
Jackson F. (1998) From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Knobe, J., Nichols, S. (eds) (2008) Experimental philosophy. Oxford University Press, New York
Lewis D. K. (1969) Convention: A philosophical study. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA
Lewis, D. K. (1970). How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy, 67, 427–446. Reprinted in Philosophical papers (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lewis, D. K. (1972). Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50, 249–258. Reprinted in Papers on metaphysics and epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nolan D. (2005) David Lewis. Acumen, Bucks
Pettit P. (1990) Virtus normativa: Rational choice perspectives. Ethics 100: 725–755
Reichenbach H. (1938) Experience and prediction. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Roth, A. S. (2010). Shared agency. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/shared-agency/.
Schelling T. (1960) The strategy of conflict. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA
Searle J. R. (1990) Collective intentions and actions. In: Cohen P. R., Morgan J., Pollack M. E. (eds) Intentions in communication. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA
Skyrms B. (1996) Evolution of the social contract. Cambridge University Press, New York
Stich S. (1990) The fragmentation of reason. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA
Sugden R. (1986) The economics of rights, cooperation and welfare. Palgrave, London
Sugden R. (2000) Team preferences. Economics and Philosophy 16: 174–204
Tuomela R. (2002) The philosophy of social practices. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Tuomela R. (2007) The philosophy of sociality: The shared point of view. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Uhlmann E. L., Pizarro D. A., Bloom P. (2008) Varieties of social cognition. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 38: 293–322
Ullmann-Margalit E. (1977) The emergence of norms. Clarendon Press, Oxford
Woodward J. (2009) Experimental investigations of social preferences. In: Kincaid H., Ross D. (eds) The Oxford handbook of the philosophy of economics. Oxford University Press, New York
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Guala, F. The normativity of Lewis Conventions. Synthese 190, 3107–3122 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0131-x
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0131-x