Skip to main content
Log in

Classical population genetics and the semantic approach to scientific theories

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In what follows, I argue that the semantic approach to scientific theories fails as a means to present the Wright–Fisher formalism (WFF) of population genetics. I offer an account of what population geneticist understand insofar as they understand the WFF, a variation on Lloyd’s view that population genetics can be understood as a family of models of mid-level generality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Beatty J. (1980) Optimal-design models and the strategy of model building in evolutionary biology. Philosophy of Science 47: 532–561

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty J. (1982) What’s wrong with the received view of evolutionary theory?. In: Asquith P. D., Giere R. N. (eds) PSA proceedings of the 1980 biennial meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association. Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, MI, pp 397–426

    Google Scholar 

  • Beatty J. (1987) On behalf of the semantic view. Biology and Philosophy 2: 17–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M. (1991) The semantic approach to evolutionary theory. Biology and Philosophy 6: 59–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewens W. J. (2004) Mathematical population genetics: 1. Theoretical introduction. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin I., Lewontin R. C. (1970) Is the gene the unit of selection?. Genetics 65: 707–734

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigord, L. D. B., Macnair, M. R., & Smithson, A. (2001). Negative frequency-dependent selection maintains a dramatic flower color polymorphism in the rewardless orchid Dactylorhiza sambucina. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of USA, 98, 6253–6255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedrick P. W. (2005) Genetics of populations. Jones and Bartlett, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerr B., Godfrey-Smith P. (2002) Individualist and multi-level perspectives on selection in structured populations. Biology and Philosophy 17: 477–517

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingman J. F. C. (1961) A matrix inequality. Quarterly Journal of Mathematics 12: 78–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, F. J., & Feldman, M. W. (1999). Evolutionary consequences of niche construction and their implications for ecology. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 96(18), 10242–10247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd E. (1983) A semantic approach to the structure of population genetics. Philosophy of Science 51: 242–264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd E. (1994) The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd E., Lewontin R. C., Feldman M. W. (2008) The generational cycle of state spaces and adequate genetical representation. Philosophy of Science 75: 140–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J. (1974) The theory of games and the evolution of animal conflicts. Journal of Theoretical Biology 47: 209–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein, R., & Skipper, R. A. (2007). Population genetics. In D. Hull & M. Ruse (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to philosophy of biology (pp. 22–43). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Rice S. (2004) Evolutionary theory: Mathematical and conceptual foundations. Sinauer and Associates, Sunderland, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Rinkevich B., Porat R., Goren M. (1995) Allorecognition elements on a urochordate histocompatibility locus indicate unprecedented extensive polymorphism. Proceedings: Biological Sciences 259: 219–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson P. (1983) The structure of evolutionary theory: A semantic approach. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 14: 215–229

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson P. (1987) A defense of the semantic conception of evolutionary theory. Biology and Philosophy 2: 26–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson P. (1988) Conceptual and logical aspects of the ‘New’ evolutionary epistemology. In: Matthen M., Linsky B. (eds) Philosophy and biology. University of Calgary Press, Calgary, AB

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson P. (1989) The structure of biological theories. State University of New York Press, Albany, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson P. (2007) Formalisations of evolutionary biology. In: Matthen M., Stephens C. (eds) Handbook of the philosophy of science, Volume 2: Philosophy of biology. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 485–524

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. (2006) Representation: The problem for structuralism. Philosophy of Science 73: 536–547

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Gildenhuys.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gildenhuys, P. Classical population genetics and the semantic approach to scientific theories. Synthese 190, 273–291 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0146-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0146-3

Keywords

Navigation