Skip to main content
Log in

Why follow the royal rule?

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This note is a sequel to Huber (Synthese 191:2167–2193, 2014). It is shown that obeying a normative principle relating counterfactual conditionals and conditional beliefs, viz. the royal rule, is a necessary and sufficient means to attaining a cognitive end that relates true beliefs in purely factual, non-modal propositions and true beliefs in purely modal propositions. Along the way I will sketch my idealism about alethic or metaphysical modality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Not everybody is willing to identify the latter two, though. See Bennett (2003).

  2. Lewis (1986a) is a realist about possible worlds, but not about counterfactual distance (Lewis 1979). Lewis (1986b, 1994) does not want to be a realist about chance.

  3. This choice may seem arbitrary, but the reader needs to keep in mind that the costs of an expressivist account of counterfactuals are huge. If counterfactuals do not express propositions, then the same is true of any theory relying on counterfactuals, such as counterfactual theories of causation, causal decision theory, dispositions, knowledge, responsibility etc.

  4. Alternatively one could pick out those factual \(\llbracket \alpha \rrbracket \)-worlds f that are \(r_w\)-minimal or no more distant according to \(r_w\) than \(f_w\) is (in the precise sense that is formalized in analogy to the definition of \(A^{r_w}\) above). This is an alternative definition, because \(f_w\) need not be assigned rank 0 by \(r_w\) and so can have a higher \(r_w\)-rank than the \(r_w\)-minimal factual \(\llbracket \alpha \rrbracket \)-worlds. In this case the resulting semantics is sound and complete with respect to the conditional logic VW that results from V by adding the axiom schema: .

  5. Herzberger (1979) shows the limit assumption to be equivalent to the condition that the set of counterfactual consequences of any consistent sentence \(\alpha \) be consistent.

  6. The weak centering assumption validates the axiom schema: . As noted in footnote 4, this axiom schema can also be validated by changing the truth-condition for the counterfactual conditional instead of making the weak centering assumption. The strong centering assumption validates the axiom schema: . This axiom schema cannot be validated by changing the truth-condition as in footnote 4.

  7. In classical Moorean sentences this additional part is a meta-disbelief about one’s first-order disbelief in A. If made explicit it gives rise to infinitely long Moorean sentences: A and I don’t believe that A and I don’t believe that I don’t believe that A etc. The auto-epistemological reflection principle (Spohn 2012, Chap. 9, relying on Hild (1998)) implies that the ideal doxastic agent is certain of what her own beliefs are. Therefore it rules that all these Moorean sentences be disbelieved, including the original one.

  8. The idea that counterfactual distances are relative to the antecedent of the counterfactual conditional under evaluation is endorsed by Bigaj (2006) and, in a different context, criticized by Cross (2008).

  9. What to do in order to avoid believing a falsehood about the modal status of a factual proposition is explained in Huber (2015b).

  10. Obviously the second claim that has been established logically implies the claim that results from the first claim by substituting ‘\(\varrho \) A-tracks the truth of A’ for ‘\(\varrho \) tracks the truth of A.’

  11. There are, of course, also the unconditional versions of probabilistic sensitivity and safety, respectively. The objective chance is high that one’s subjective credence in A is high given that A is true. For all \(A\subseteq W\) and all \(v\in W\), \(ch_v\left( \left\{ x\in W:cr_x\left( A\right) =high\right\} \mid A\right) =high\). The objective chance equals c that A is true given that one’s subjective credence in A equals c. For all \(A\subseteq W\) and all \(v\in W\), \(ch_v\left( A\mid \left\{ x\in W:cr_x\left( A\right) =c\right\} \right) =c\).

References

  • Adams, E. W. (1970). Subjunctive and indicative conditionals. Foundations of Language, 6, 89–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, E. W. (1975). The logic of conditionals. An application of probability to deductive logic. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bigaj, T. (2006). Non-locality and possible worlds: A counterfactual perspective on quantum entanglement. Frankfurt: Ontos.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Briggs, R. (2009). The big bad bug bites anti-realists about chance. Synthese, 167, 81–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. (2003). A philosophical guide to conditionals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1947). Meaning and necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, J., Hall, N., & Paul, L. A. (2004) (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Cross, C. B. (2008). Antecedent-relative comparative world similarity. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 37, 101–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edgington, D. (2008). Counterfactuals. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 108, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1978). A note on Jeffrey conditionalization. Philosophy of Science, 45, 361–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldszmidt, M., & Judea, J. P. (1996). Qualitative probabilities for default reasoning, belief revision, and causal modeling. Artificial Intelligence, 84, 57–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herzberger, H. G. (1979). Counterfactuals and consistency. Journal of Philosophy, 76, 83–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hild, M. (1998). Auto-epistemology and updating. Philosophical Studies, 92, 321–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hild, M., & Spohn, W. (2008). The measurement of ranks and the laws of iterated contraction. Artificial Intelligence, 172, 1195–1218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2006). Ranking functions and rankings on languages. Artificial Intelligence, 170, 462–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2007). The consistency argument for ranking functions. Studia Logica, 86, 299–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2013). Structural equations and beyond. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 6, 709–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2014). New foundations for counterfactuals. Synthese, 191, 2167–2193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2015a). How to Learn concepts, consequences, and conditionals. Analytica, 1, 20–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2015b). What should I believe about what would have been the case? Journal of Philosophical Logic, 44, 81–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1896). The will to believe. In F. Burkhardt, F. Bowers, & I. Skrupskelis (Eds.), The will to believe and other essays in popular philosophy (pp. 291–341). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. C. (1983). The logic of decision (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1973a). Counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1973b). Causation. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 556–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1979). Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Noûs, 13, 455–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1980). A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. In R. C. Jeffrey (Ed.), Studies in inductive logic and probability (Vol. II, pp. 263–293). Berkeley: University of Berkeley Press. Reprinted with Postscripts in D. Lewis (1986), Philosophical papers (Vol. II, pp. 83–132). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Lewis, D. K. (1986a). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1986b). Introduction. In D. Lewis (Ed.), Philosophical papers II (pp. ix–xvii). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Lewis, D. K. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. Mind, 103, 473–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1942). A reply to my critics. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of G. E. Moore (pp. 535–677). La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrew, R. (2013). A new epistemic utility argument for the principal principle. Episteme, 10, 19–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roush, S. (2005). Tracking truth: Knowledge, evidence, and science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shenoy, P. P. (1991). On Spohn’s rule for revision of beliefs. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning, 5, 149–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1999). How to defeat opposition to Moore. Philosophical Perspectives, 13, 141–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (1988). Ordinal conditional functions: A dynamic theory of epistemic states. In W. L. Harper & B. Skyrms (Eds.), Causation in decision, belief change, and statistics II (pp. 105–134). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2012). The laws of belief. Ranking theory and its philosophical applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2013). A ranking-theoretic Approach to conditionals. Cognitive Science, 37, 1074–1106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2015). Conditionals: A unifying ranking-theoretic perspective. Philosophers’ Imprint, 15, 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. C. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in Lry. American philosophical quaterly (Vol. 2, pp. 98–112). Monograph series. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Vineberg, S. (2000). The logical status of conditionalization and its role in confirmation. In N. Shanks & R. B. Gardner (Eds.), Logic, probability and science. Poznan studies in the philosophy of the science and humanities (Vol. 71, pp. 77–94). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Jonathan Weisberg as well as three anonymous reviewers for their constructive feedback, and to Kevin Kuhl for proof-reading an earlier version of this paper. My research was supported by the Canadian SSHRC through its Insight program and by the Connaught Foundation through its New Researcher program.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Franz Huber.

Appendix

Appendix

Someone interested in studying safety, and not bothered by Huber’s (2014) thought that it is important to distinguish between the factual components \(f_w\) and the modal components \(r_w\) of a possible world w, will find the following models more elegant: \(\left( W,\left( R_w\right) _{w\in W},\left( S_w\right) _{w\in W}\right) \), where W is a non-empty set of possible worlds, \(\left( R_w\right) _{w\in W}\) is a family of arbitrary functions from \(\wp \left( W\right) \) into \({\mathbb {N}}\cup \left\{ \infty \right\} \), and \(\left( S_w\right) _{w\in W}\) is a family of regular subjective ranking functions from \(\wp \left( W\right) \) into \({\mathbb {N}}\cup \left\{ \infty \right\} \).

In this set-up the royal rule says: for all \(v\in W\) and all \(A\subseteq W\), and all “vA-admissible” propositions \(E\subseteq W\),

$$\begin{aligned} S_v\left( A\mid \left\{ w\in W:R_w\left( A\right) =n\right\} \cap E\right) =n. \end{aligned}$$

With the right assumptions about admissibility it follows from these assumptions that \(R_w\) is a ranking function for each \(w\in W\). In particular, the condition from sections 3 and 4 that \(r_w\) be a ranking function is not an assumption of the present paper, but rather a consequence of the royal rule that I have taken for granted to simplify the presentation of this paper (for a derivation see Huber 2014).

In this set-up, instead of considering cases \(\omega \) one considers possible worlds \(w=\left( \llbracket \rrbracket _w,R_w,S_w\right) \). Sensitivity says: for all \(v\in W\) and all \(A\subseteq W\), all A-worlds w that are \(R_v\)-minimal are such that \(S_w\left( A\right) =0\). Adherence says: for all \(v\in W\) and all \(A\subseteq W\), all A-worlds w that are \(R_v\)-minimal are such that \(S_w\left( W{\setminus } A\right) >0\). Safety says: for all \(v\in W\) and all \(A\subseteq W\), A is true in all \(R_v\)-minimal worlds w in which \(S_w\left( W{\setminus } A\right) >0\).

One conditional version of sensitivity says: for all \(v\in W\) and all \(A\subseteq W\), all A-worlds w that are \(R_v\)-minimal are such that

$$\begin{aligned} S_w\left( A\mid \left\{ x\in W:R_x\left( A\right) =R_w\left( A\right) \right\} \cap E\right) =0 \end{aligned}$$

for all “wA-admissible” \(E\subseteq W\). One conditional version of adherence says: for all \(v\in W\) and all \(A\subseteq W\), all A-worlds w that are \(R_v\)-minimal are such that

$$\begin{aligned} S_w\left( W{\setminus } A\mid \left\{ x\in W:R_x\left( W{\setminus } A\right) =R_w\left( W{\setminus } A\right) \right\} \cap E\right) >0 \end{aligned}$$

for all “\(w,\left( W{\setminus } A\right) \)-admissible” \(E\subseteq W\). One conditional version of safety says: for all \(v\in W\) and all \(A\subseteq W\), A is true in all \(R_v\)-minimal worlds w in which

$$\begin{aligned} S_w\left( W{\setminus } A\mid \left\{ x\in W:R_x\left( W{\setminus } A\right) =R_w\left( W{\setminus } A\right) \right\} \cap E\right) >0 \end{aligned}$$

for some “\(w,\left( W{\setminus } A\right) \)-admissible” \(E\subseteq W\).

These conditional versions consider the truth about the modal status of A in the word w the agent is in. Quite different conditional versions consider the truth about the modal status of A in the world v where the counterfactual conditional is evaluated. The conditions studied in this paper considered if the agent believes A in w conditional on what is true about the modal status of A in the world w she is in. The different conditions consider if she believes A in w conditional on what is true about the modal status of A elsewhere, in a different possible world v.

One way to think of the former conditions is in terms of what is true from the first person perspective of the agent, and to think of the latter conditions in terms of what is true from the third person perspective of some tracking-ascriber. The latter conditional versions of sensitivity and adherence and safety say: for all \(v\in W\) and all \(A\subseteq W\), all A-worlds w that are \(R_v\)-minimal are such that \(S_w\left( A\mid \left\{ x\in W:R_x\left( A\right) =R_v\left( A\right) \right\} \cap E\right) =0\) for all “vA-admissible” \(E\subseteq W\). And: for all \(v\in W\) and all \(A\subseteq W\), all A-worlds w that are \(R_v\)-minimal are such that \(S_w\left( W{\setminus } A\mid \left\{ x\in W:R_x\left( W{\setminus } A\right) =R_v\left( W{\setminus } A\right) \right\} \cap E\right) >0\) for all “\(v,\left( W{\setminus } A\right) \)-admissible” \(E\subseteq W\). As well as: for all \(v\in W\) and all \(A\subseteq W\), A is true in all \(R_v\)-minimal worlds w in which \(S_w\left( W{\setminus } A\mid \left\{ x\in W:R_x\left( W{\setminus } A\right) =R_v\left( W{\setminus } A\right) \right\} \cap E\right) >0\) for some “\(v,\left( W{\setminus } A\right) \)-admissible” \(E\subseteq W\).

Bayesians may want to interpret \(R_w\) as the objective chance distribution of world w, \(ch_w\), and \(S_w\) as the ideal doxastic agent’s subjective credence function in w, \(cr_w\) (as well as change the domain and range to some suitable algebra as well as the unit interval, respectively). On this probabilistic interpretation the royal rule becomes Lewis’ (1980) principal principle, and the probabilistically re-interpreted set-up allows one to study which ends the principal principle furthers (Pettigrew 2013 is an excellent study of this kind). In addition one can study which norms further the following cognitive ends that also consider what is true about the chance of A from the third person perspective mentioned above:

  • The objective chance is high that one’s subjective credence in A conditional on the truth about the objective chance of A is high given that A is true. For all \(A\subseteq W\) and all \(v\in W\) and all “vA-admissible” \(E\subseteq W\), \(ch_v\left( cr\left( A\mid \left\{ x\in W:ch_x\left( A\right) =ch_v\left( A\right) \right\} \cap E\right) =high\mid A\right) =high\).

  • The objective chance equals c that A is true given that one’s subjective credence in A conditional on the truth about the objective chance of A equals c. For all \(A\subseteq W\) and all \(v\in W\) and all “ vA-admissible” \(E\subseteq W\), \(ch_v\left( A\mid cr\left( A\mid \left\{ x\in W:ch_x\left( A\right) =ch_v\left( A\right) \right\} \cap E\right) =c\right) =c\).

Here \(cr\left( A\mid C\right) =high\) is the proposition \(\left\{ x\in W:cr_x\left( A\mid C\right) =high\right\} \).

Of course, in this more elegant and general set-up, it is not possible anymore to say that admissible information is purely modal information, as we have done in this paper. The reason is that, in this more elegant and general set-up, the very distinction between factual information and modal information cannot be drawn without further assumptions. Admissibility now is relative to a proposition and a world (and, of course, a credence function), and this is only the tip of the iceberg that is known as the “big bad bug” (Rachael 2009) and that is the reason for Huber’s (2014) complicated set-up in the first place.Footnote 11

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Huber, F. Why follow the royal rule?. Synthese 194, 1565–1590 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-1004-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-1004-x

Keywords

Navigation