Skip to main content
Log in

The ontological and epistemological superiority of hylomorphism

  • S.I.: Materialism & Metaphysics
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Materialism—the view that all of reality is wholly determined by the very, very small—and extreme nominalism—the view that properties, kinds, and qualities do not really exist—have been the dominant view in analytic philosophy for the last 100 years or so. Both views, however, have failed to provide adequate accounts for the possibility of intentionality and of knowledge. We must therefore look to alternatives. One well-tested alternative, the hylomorphism of Aristotle and the medieval scholastics, was rejected without being refuted and so deserves further examination. I will argue that Aristotelian hylomorphic provides a markedly superior account of knowledge, cognitive normativity, and intentionality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As will be clear below, by ‘hylomorphism’ I mean what I have called ‘staunch hylomorphism’ (Koons 2014), as opposed to the ‘faint-hearted’ hylomorphism represented by the work of Fine (1999), Johnston (2006), and Koslicki (2008), and discussed by Williams (1986). My fellow staunch hylomorphists include Scaltsas (1994), Rea (2011), Marmodoro (2013), and Jaworski (2016). Staunch hylomorphism combines a sparse theory of fundamental entities and material composition, a sparse theory of properties, and a robustly non-Humean theory of causal powers.

  2. The form of grounding that I have in mind follows closely the work of Fine (2012) and Rosen (2010). On these views, grounding is fundamentally a relation between facts. I will also assume that the existence of the grounding fact necessitates what it grounds, and that grounding is an asymmetric relation.

  3. I also argued in Koons (2000) that materialism cannot explain the reliability of our inferences to the simplest or most elegant hypothesis in fundamental physics, since materialism excludes the possibility that such simplicity is a non-accidental, projectible feature of the laws.

  4. Millikan (1984, p. 28). Millikan’s actual definition requires that C be a “Normal” or reproductively established characteristic of R. Instead of requiring that C be positively correlated in R with the function F, she requires only that the positive correlation hold in some set S which includes x’s ancestors, together with “other things not having C.” Her exact wording of clause (3) is:

    One among the legitimate explanations that can be given of the fact that x exists makes reference to the fact that C correlated positively with F [i.e., the function of producing E in circumstances I] over S, either directly causing reproduction of x or explaining why R was proliferated and hence why x exists.

    None of these variations would make any difference to our objection.

  5. From “Criticism on ‘The Origin of Species”’, Natural History Review, 1864, p. 7.

  6. In a recent article (Koons 2014), I have developed an account of how such fundamental causal powers of composite substances could be realized in a world like ours.

  7. See Anderson (1972), Sewell (1985, pp. 3–9), Morrison (2006).

References

  • Anderson, P. (1972). More is different. Science, 177(4047), 393–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bealer, G. (2010). The self-consciousness argument. In Koons & Bealer (Eds)., The waning of materialism: New essays (pp. 137–158). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Beilby, J. (2002). Naturalism defeated? Essays on Plantinga’s evolutionary argument against naturalism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J. (2015). Grasping the third realm. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford Studies in epistemology (Vol 5, pp. 1–38). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Boyd, R. (1988). How to be a moral realist. In G. Sayre-McCord (Ed.), Essays on moral realism (pp. 187–228). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1999). Things and their parts. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 23, 61–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2012). Guide to ground. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical grounding (pp. 37–80). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1969). Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. Journal of Philosophy, 66, 829–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. L. (1973). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hendry, H. (2010). Ontological reduction and molecular structure. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 41, 183–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaworski, W. (2016). The structure and metaphysics of mind: How hylomorphism solves the mind–body problem. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (2006). Hylomorphism. The Journal of Philosophy, 103, 652–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1988). What is naturalized epistemology? In J. E. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives (Vol. 2, pp. 381–406). Asascadero, CA: Ridgeview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2007). Physicalism, or something near enough. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Koons, R. C. (2000). The incompatibility of naturalism and scientific realism. In W. L. Craig & J. P. Moreland (Eds.), Naturalism: A critical analysis (pp. 49–63). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koons, R. C. (2010). Epistemological problems with materialism. In Koons & Bealer (Eds.). (pp. 281–308).

  • Koons, R. C. (2014). Staunch vs. faint-hearted hylomorphism: Toward an Aristotelian account of composition. Res Philosophica, 91, 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koons, R. C. (2016). The general argument from intuition. In T. Dougherty & J. Walls (Eds.), Two dozen (or so) arguments for God’s existence: The Plantinga project. Oxford: Oxford University Press. forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koons, R. C., & Bealer, G. (Eds.). (2010). The waning of materialism: New essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koons, R. C., & Pruss, A. R. (2017). Must a functionalist be an Aristotelian? In J. Jonathan (Ed.), Causal powers. Oxford: Oxford University Press. forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korman, D. Z. (2014). Debunking perceptual beliefs about ordinary objects. Philosophers’ Imprint, 14(13), 1–21.

  • Koslicki, K. (2008). The structure of objects. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Lewis, C. S. (1947). Miracles: A preliminary study. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1974). Radical interpretation. Synthese, 27, 331–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Madrell, S. H. P. (1998). Why are there no insects in the open sea? The Journal of Experimental Biology, 201, 2461–2464.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmodoro, A. (2013). Aristotle’s hylomorphism, without reconditioning. Philosophical Inquiry, 26, 5–22.

  • Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories: New foundations for realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molnar, G. (2003). Powers: A study in metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2006). Emergence, reduction and theoretical principles: Rethinking fundamentalism. Philosophy of Science, 73, 876–887.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and proper function. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. (1986). Contemporary theories of knowledge (1st ed.). Towota, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rea, M. C. (2002). World without design: The ontological consequences of naturalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rea, M. (2011). Hylomorphism reconditioned. Philosophical Perspectives (Metaphysics), 25, 341–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2010). Metaphysical dependence: Grounding and reduction. In B. Hale & A. Hoffman (Eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, logic, and epistemology (pp. 109–136). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scaltsas, T. (1994). Substances and universals in Aristotle’s metaphysics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schechter, J. (2010). The reliability challenge and the epistemology of logic. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 437–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1980). Minds, brains and programs. Behavioral and brain sciences, 3, 417–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (2003). Social ontology and political power. In F. R. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing metaphysics: The nature of social reality (pp. 195–210). Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sewell, G. L. (1985). Quantum theory of collective phenomena. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2007). Ceteris paribus conditionals and comparative normalcy. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 36, 97–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2009). Evolution and the normativity of epistemic reasons. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 39(sup1), 213–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toepfer, G. (2012). Teleology and its constitutive role for biology as the science of organized systems in nature. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 113–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1986). Hylomorphism. In J. Annas (Ed.), Oxford studies in ancient philosophy (Vol. IV, pp. 189–199). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert C. Koons.

Additional information

I gratefully acknowledge with the support given me during the 2014–2015 academic year by the James Madison Program in American Ideals and Institutions at Princeton University, and by the University Research Institute at the University of Texas at Austin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Koons, R.C. The ontological and epistemological superiority of hylomorphism. Synthese 198 (Suppl 3), 885–903 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1295-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1295-6

Keywords

Navigation