Skip to main content
Log in

Whose purposes? Biological teleology and intentionality

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Teleosemantic theories aspire to develop a naturalistic account of intentional agency and thought by appeal to biological teleology. In particular, most versions of teleosemantics study the emergence of intentionality in terms of biological purposes introduced by Darwinian evolution. The aim of this paper is to argue that the sorts of biological purposes identified by these evolutionary approaches do not allow for a satisfactory account of intentionality. More precisely, I claim that such biological purposes should be attributed to reproductive chains or lineages, rather than to individual traits or organisms, whereas the purposes underlying intentional agency and thought are typically attributed to individuals. In the last part of the paper I suggest that related difficulties are also faced, despite appearances, by accounts of intentionality relying on alternative organizational approaches to biological teleology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Arguably, there may be intentional states that do not target real world objects or properties (e.g. fictional thinking). In this paper, however, I focus on intentional states that are about features of the external world.

  2. Of course, it is an open possibility to give an observer-dependent explanation of biological teleology and then to try to account for the intentionality of the relevant observers in a way that does not presuppose biological purposes. For instance, one could argue that intentionality emerges with complex socio-linguistic practices (see Brandom 1994). Although this is an interesting possibility, in this paper I leave it aside and I focus instead on the project of accounting for intentionality in terms of biological teleology.

  3. I am calling this view, on the one hand, evolutionary because it appeals to Darwinian evolution in order to account for biological purposes; on the other hand, it is called etiological because it accounts for the purposes of entities in terms of the etiology (i.e. causal history) of such entities, in contrast to other evolutionary accounts that focus on current or future contributions to fitness [for instance, the propensity account defended by Bigelow and Pargetter (1987) and Canfield (1964)]. As I will discuss below, organizational views (for instance, Mossio and Bich 2017; Mossio et al. 2009; Christensen and Bickhard 2002) can be counted as etiological, even if not evolutionary, insofar as they consider the causal contribution of a current purposive trait to maintaining the conditions necessary for the existence of that very same trait.

  4. I will use the terms ‘selective pressures’ to refer to whatever forces or mechanisms by virtue of which selective reinforcement is produced (i.e. these forces contribute to preserving/inhibiting the persistence of the things under selection).

  5. The view I want to examine here is that purposes can be introduced by selective processes, not that this is the only way in which purposes can arise.

  6. It may be argued that entities are sometimes evaluated in certain ways by virtue of being tokens of a certain type. So, murder as a type act is wrong, which makes each token act of murder wrong. Note however that, still, each token act of murder is taken to be wrong as a token act, and that therefore agents will be disposed to address sanctions to the specific individual responsible for a particular token-act of murder. In the case of natural selection, in contrast, it is common that the token trait that fails to achieve a biological goal is not sanctioned or reinforced in any way: the only reinforcing pressures affect the potential offspring of the organism that token trait belongs to.

  7. Assume that sanctioning others is not an indirect way of sanctioning the individual in question (you could punish someone indirectly by punishing her friends, since this will presumably upset her).

  8. In a similar spirit, Foot argues that teleological thinking in relation to Darwinian evolution involves regarding species as time-extended organisms: ‘In such contexts it is supposed to make sense to speak of the good of a species, as if a species were itself a gradually developing, one-off organism, whose life might stretch for millions of years. Perhaps the extinction of a species is imagined as a kind of death, and therefore as if it were an evil, with that which makes for its continuance thought of as ‘for its good’!’ (2001, p. 32, fn. 37). The thesis that species should be thought of as time-extended individuals has been defended by Ghiselin (1974) and Hull (1976).

  9. One may object that the difficulty faced by etiological-evolutionary views also arises here, under a new guise. The problem would be that the purposes introduced by the interactions of self-maintaining organism with their environments cannot be attributed to momentary time-slices of token traits or organisms, but rather to time-extended sections of those tokens, since what is sustained in the relevant interaction is such time-extended entities and not momentary time-slices of the interacting organism (in other words, the evaluative pressures associated with the interaction do not target momentary time-slices, but time-extended entities). However, I do not take this to be a problem. It is very plausible to think that, in general, purposes can only be attributed to subjects with a sufficient temporal extension. It seems that it does not make sense to attribute goals to entities whose existence lacks temporal duration—and that therefore cannot guide their behavior in pursuit of those goals, or track the progress of such purposive endeavors. At any rate, in general intentional agency is underlain by goals of time-extended individuals, and not merely of some of their momentary time-slices.

References

  • Artiga, M., & Martínez, M. (2016). The organizational account of function is an etiological account of function. Acta biotheoretica, 64, 105–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barandarian, X., & Egbert, N. (2014). Norm-establishing and norm-following in aoutonomous agency. Artificial Life, 20, 5–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. (1991). Can biological teleology be naturalized? The Journal of Philosophy, 88, 647–655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L., Mossio, M., Ruiz-Mirazo, K., & Moreno, A. (2016). Biological regulation: Controlling the system from within. Biology and Philosophy, 31, 237–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, J., & Pargetter, R. (1987). Functions. The Journal of Philosophy, 84(4), 181–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (1998). Ruling passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (2010). Practical tortoise raising: And other philosophical essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1976). Wright on functions. Philosophical Review, 85, 70–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (2002). A rebuttal on functions. In A. R. Ariew, R. Cummins, & M. Perlman (Eds.), Functions (pp. 63–12). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunnander, B. (2011). On the theoretical motivation for positing etiological functions. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 41(3), 371–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2009). Primitive agency and natural norms. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79(2), 251–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Canfield, J. (1964). Teleological explanation in biology. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 14(56), 285–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, W. (2012). Natural sources of normativity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43(1), 104–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, W., & Bickhard, M. H. (2002). The process dynamics of normative function. The Monist, 85, 3–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, P. S. (2000). Malfunctions. Biology and Philosophy, 15(1), 19–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, P. S. (2001). The excesses of teleosemantics. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 31, 117–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Prado, G., Salas, J., & Zamora-Bonilla, J. (2015). Collective actors without collective minds: An inferentialist approach. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 45(1), 3–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delancey, C. (2006). Ontology and teleofunctions: A defense and revision of the systematic account of teleological explanation. Synthese, 150, 69–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (2001). Natural goodness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (1974). A radical solution to the species problem. Systematic Biology, 23(4), 536–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (2003). Thinking how to live. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1996). Complexity and the function of mind in nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1993). Functional analysis and proper functions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 44(3), 409–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1976). Are species really individuals? Systematic Biology, 25(2), 174–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1989). Dispositional theories of value. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 63, 139–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1968). Biological foundations of individuality. International Philosophical Quarterly, 8(2), 231–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1989). Dispositional theories of value. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 63, 113–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1998). Mind, value, and reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, P. (2009). Functions and norms. In U. Krohs & P. Kroes (Eds.), Functions in biological and artificial worlds: Comparative philosophical perspectives (pp. 93–102). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundation for realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1989). Biosemantics. The Journal of Philosophy, 86, 281–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (2005). Language: A biological model. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., & Bich, L. (2017). What makes biological organisation teleological? Synthese, 194(4), 1089–1114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., Saborido, C., & Moreno, A. (2009). An organizational account of biological functions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(4), 813–841.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1991). Functions as selected effects: The conceptual analyst’s defense. Philosophy of Science, 58, 168–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1995). Misrepresenting and malfunctioning. Philosophical Studies, 79(2), 109–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (1987). Reality and representation. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (1993). Philosophical Naturalism. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. M. (1992). Intentionality and teleological error. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 73(3), 267–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J. (2009). Not by design: Retiring Darwin’s watchmaker. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2000). Teleology: Yesterday, today, and tomorrow? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 31(1), 213–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saborido, C., Mossio, M., & Moreno, A. (2011). Biological organization and cross-generation functions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 583–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. (1993). Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2010). Knowing full well. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2008). Constructivism about reasons. Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 3, 207-45.

  • Street, S. (2010). What is constructivism in ethics and metaethics? Philosophy Compass, 5(5), 363–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2013). Social ontology: Collective intentionality and group agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. M. (2008). Teleology. In M. Ruse (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of biology (pp. 113–137). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A., & Varela, J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (1998). The essence of response-dependence. European Review of Philosophy, 3, 31–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (1987). Needs, values, truth: Essays in the philosophy of value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. (1976). Teleological explanations: An etiological analysis of goals and functions. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Marc Artiga, Manuel Heras-Escribano, Manolo Martínez, Cristian Saborido, Jonathan Way and Daniel Whiting for their comments and feedback. I am also grateful to audiences at the University of Southampton, the iCog conference at the University of Sheffielf and the VI Research Workshop on Philosophy of Biology and Cognitive Sciences at the University of Barcelona. This work has been supported by the DGI, Spanish Government, research project FFI2014-57258-P (Normative inferences and interferences in scientific research).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Javier González de Prado Salas.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

González de Prado Salas, J. Whose purposes? Biological teleology and intentionality. Synthese 195, 4507–4524 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1416-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1416-x

Keywords

Navigation