Skip to main content
Log in

Structures, dynamics and mechanisms in neuroscience: an integrative account

  • S.I.: Neuroscience and Its Philosophy
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Proponents of mechanistic explanations have recently proclaimed that all explanations in the neurosciences appeal to mechanisms. The purpose of the paper is to critically assess this statement and to develop an integrative account that connects a large range of both mechanistic and dynamical explanations. I develop and defend four theses about the relationship between dynamical and mechanistic explanations: that dynamical explanations are structurally grounded, that they are multiply realizable, possess realizing mechanisms and provide a powerful top-down heuristic. Four examples shall support my points: the harmonic oscillator, the Haken–Kelso–Bunz model of bimanual coordination, the Watt governor and the Gierer–Meinhardt model of biological pattern formation. I also develop the picture of “horizontal” and “vertical” directions of explanations to illustrate the different perspectives of the dynamical and mechanistic approach as well as their potential integration by means of intersection points.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Cf. Izhikevich (2007) and Gerstner et al. (2014) for applications of dynamical systems theory in neuroscience and Brauer and Kribs (2016) for biology in general.

  2. As a reviewer has pointed out, the assumption that generalizability and scope are explanatory virtues is already controversial and should particularly be argued for. While a general discussion of the nature of scientific explanation is beyond the scope of the present paper, I like to add this much: explanation raises understanding, hence, an explanatory pattern with a wider scope raises a bigger understanding than with a narrow scope. So far, I take sides with the basic idea of unificationism. I do, on the other hand, agree that many of the well-known standard problems of the classic DN- and unificationist approach stem from the fact that causation has not suitably been taken into account. The purpose of the present approach (and the present section in particular) is to present an integrated picture of a “horizontal” and a “vertical” direction of explanation and to eventually stress the idea that a full-fledged understanding of many phenomena is only brought forth once we understand their particular mechanistic realizations as well as their deep and generalizable structural core. In this respect, the present approach is in general harmony with a recent paper by Bangu (2017) who presents a revised unificationist account that aims to incorporate the causal account as a sub-component.

  3. Of course, as Bechtel (2009) for instance discusses, the possibility of conservation of mechanisms through evolutionary descent allows for a certain, limited generalization of mechanistic explanations.

  4. Note that what is ‘predicted’ here is the existence of a mechanism of a certain type (the GM type, i.e. with a structural core represented by the GM model equations). For instance, to take a most recent research result, the particular GM-type mechanism responsible for the color and pattern of skin scales in lizards (Manukyan et al. 2017). The prediction of mechanism types serves as a research heuristics and should of course not be conflated with the prediction of the temporal evolution of a certain system (e.g. by means of its underlying dynamical equations). To consider prediction in this latter sense as already explanatory is highly controversial (and of course dismissed by most mechanists). But it should be clear that this is a different sense of prediction than what I have in mind here.

References

  • Bangu, S. (2017). Scientific explanation and understanding: Unificationism reconsidered. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 7(1), 103–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2009). Generalization and discovery by assuming conserved mechanisms: Cross-species research on circadian oscillators. Philosophy of Science, 76, 762–773.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biology and Biomedical Sciences, 36(2), 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2010). Dynamic mechanistic explanation: Computational modeling of circadian rhythms as an exemplar for cognitive science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41, 321–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brauer, F., & Kribs, C. (2016). Dynamical systems for biological modeling: An introduction. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). After the philosophy of mind: Replacing scholasticism with science. Philosophy of Science, 75, 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. & Kaplan, D. M. (2011). Towards a mechanistic philosophy of neuroscience: A Mechanistic Approach. In: S. French, & J. Saatsi (eds.) The continuum companion to the philosophy of science, Continuum.

  • Dizadji-Bahmani, F., Frigg, R., & Hartmann, S. (2010). Who’s afraid of Nagelian reduction? Erkenntnis, 73, 393–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eigen, M. (1971). Selforganization of matter and the evolution of biological macromolecules. Die Naturwissenschaften, 58(10), 465–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felline, L. (2015). Mechanisms meet structural explanation. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0746-9.

  • Gerstner, W., Kistler, W. M., Naud, R., & Paninski, L. (2014). Neuronal dynamics. From single neurons to networks and models of cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gierer, A., & Meinhardt, H. (1972). A theory of biological pattern formation. Kybernetik, 12, 30–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haken, H., Kelso, J. A. S., & Bunz, H. (1985). A theoretical model of phase transitions in human hand movements. Biological Cybernetics, 51, 347–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Izhikevich, E. M. (2007). Dynamical systems in neuroscience: The geometry of excitability and bursting. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M. (2011). Explanation and description in computational neuroscience. Synthese, 183, 339–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M. (2015). Moving parts: The natural alliance between dynamical and mechanistic modeling approaches. Biology and Philosophy, 30, 757–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M., & Craver, C. F. (2011). The explanatory force of dynamical and mathematical models in neuroscience: A mechanistic perspective. Philosophy of Science, 78, 601–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhlmann, M. (2014). Explaining financial markets in terms of complex systems. Philosophy of Science, 81, 1117–1130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A., & Bechtel, W. (2013). Abstraction and the organization of mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 80(2), 241–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyre, H. (2009). The “Multirealization” of multiple realizability. In A. Hieke & H. Leitgeb (Eds.), Reduction–abstraction–analysis (pp. 79–94). Frankfurt: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P. K., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meinhardt, H. (1982). Models of biological pattern formation. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manukyan, L., Montandon, S. A., Fofonjka, A., Smirnov, S., & Milinkovitch, M. C. (2017). A living mesoscopic cellular automaton made of skin scales. Nature, 544, 173–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, L. N. (2015). Dynamical models and explanation in neuroscience. Philosophy of Science, 81(1), 32–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schöner, G., & Kelso, S. (1988). Dynamic pattern generation in behavioral and neural systems. Science, 239, 1513–1520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schuster, P. (2011). Physical principles of evolution. In H. Meyer-Ortmanns & S. Thurner (Eds.), Principles of evolution. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stepp, N., Chemero, A., & Turvey, M. T. (2011). Philosophy for the rest of cognitive science. Topics in Cognitive Science, 3, 425–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zednik, C. (2011). The nature of dynamical explanation. Philosophy of Science, 78, 238–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to Carlos Zednik and two anonymous reviewers for valuable inputs and comments that helped to improve the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Holger Lyre.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lyre, H. Structures, dynamics and mechanisms in neuroscience: an integrative account. Synthese 195, 5141–5158 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1616-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1616-4

Keywords

Navigation