Skip to main content
Log in

Multiplicity and indiscernibility

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The indistinguishability of bosons and fermions has been an essential part of our ideas of quantum mechanics since the 1920s. But what is the mathematical basis for this indistinguishability? An answer was provided in the group representation theory that developed alongside quantum theory and quickly became a major part of its mathematical structure. In the 1930s such a complex and seemingly abstract theory came to be rejected by physicists as the standard functional analysis picture presented by John von Neumann (in his book Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics) took hold. The purpose of the present account is to show how indistinguishability is explained within representation theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In Leibniz’s own words this is the principle that ‘It is not true that two substances may be exactly alike and differ only numerically, solo numero [only in number].’ Discourse on Metaphysics, IX, from 1678.

  2. This was then argued for bosons in Muller and Seevinck (2009). Such ideas were initially worked out by Saunders in a series of papers (see his 2003b) and presented for philosophers in Saunders (2006) and, more recently, (2016). Saunders believes bosons, in contrast to fermions, are not objects at all. Muller has come to adopt a structuralist view of both bosons and fermions (Muller 2011, 2015). They are united in their belief in non-reductive relations.

  3. Several people were responsible for the post-war revival, most notably G. W. Mackey, e.g. in his (1951, 1978), Giorgio Racah (see Fano and Racah 1959; Biedenharn and Louck 1981); Messiah in his (1962) and the continuing work of Wigner (his 1959). See also Khinchin (1960).

  4. A common feature of many of these simplifications came from dealing with only two identical particles, with the result that only two permutations in the symmetric group \(\mathfrak {S}_{2}\) needed to be considered, one of these being the identity, the other being an exchange. But \(\mathfrak {S}_{2}\) has properties not shared by symmetric groups of higher order, because it is a commutative group with a trivial representation theory in which all irreducible representations are one-dimensional. This is picked up in Sects. 2 and 3.

  5. The copying of this text in Muller and Saunders is not exact. Though the discrepancies are not serious, they have been corrected here.

  6. The book that Muller and Saunders seize upon was in fact written in 1926 and scarcely revised for its 1949 english translation, as Weyl noted in essay 9, p. 220, of Weyl (2009). It doesn’t properly represent his view in 1930, let alone 1949.

  7. It is symptomatic of the quality of the English translation that the word ‘Eigenwert’, i.e. eigenvalue, is used four times in the German original and not at all in the English. However the more accurate modern term would be ‘weight’, which had little currency in 1930, being coined by Cartan and made popular later by Bourbaki (see section 4). In the disputed paragraph Robertson repeats the word ‘permuted’ which is definitely a mistake, and does not occur in the German.

  8. Adding the half-integer spin cases by tensoring an even-dimensional module with that coming from \(\,GL_{n}\) will give one the complete pure states required for electrons: two electrons being allowed for any given value of the energy. Then the Pauli exclusion principle says that a measurement cannot result in two particles in the same complete eigenstate—because, again, the eigenvalues do not have any multiplicity in the space.

  9. Thus he speaks, also in Weyl (1949), of the ‘Leibniz–Pauli exclusion principle’: eigenstates must be distinct: distinguishability of eigenvalues implies their non-identity.

  10. Margenau (1944) likewise held that ‘the E.P., so far as it goes, contradicts Leibniz [PII].’ p. 202. Compare with Saunders (2003b, p. 294). However it is incorrect to say that Margenau was the first to note this.

  11. The antisymmetric space is also often called, and will often be hereafter, the exterior power, \(\bigwedge ^{r} (V^{n})\), and the symmetric space is often called the symmetric power, \(\text{ Sym }^{r} (V^{n})\).

  12. Nor does the field need to be \(\,\mathbb {C}\,\)—the theorem will continue to hold in an algebraically closed field of any characteristic.

  13. This was generalised to countable dimension vector spaces in Dixmier (1981).

  14. Burnside’s work was first presented in Burnside (1905) and Frobenius and Schur’s extension in their (Frobenius and Schur 1906). See Burnside (1951) appendix I for a summary; also foundational is Schur (1905). However Burnside’s theorem was known to Weyl, von Neumann, Wigner and other German mathematicians largely through Frobenius and Schur’s paper, so I call it, as they sometimes did, the Burnside–Schur–Frobenius theorem. The ring-theoretic version of the theorem may have been due originally to Emmy Noether or Emil Artin. See Artin’s later (1950) for discussion. It was known to von Neumann in his (1929), and is the basis for his work in “rings of operators”; and, of course, to Weyl in his (1929) (1931) and (1939)—but note Weyl avoids using the word ‘ring’ and throughout prefers the word ‘algebra’. See footnote 9 to ch. III of Weyl (1931). The theorem was then generalised by Jacobson and Chevalley into what was called the Density theorem, a fundamental result in ring theory. For modern proofs of the theorem see Lam (1998) or the more recent Radjabalipour et al. (2004).

    The importance of Burnside’s theorem is hard to overstate. Von Neumann gave a copy of the Frobenius and Schur paper to Eugene Wigner, of which the latter said that it “had an enormous effect on me.” (From an interview that Wigner gave on his years at the IAS, at https://web.archive.org/web/20121005061854/https://www.princeton.edu/~mudd/finding_aids/mathoral/pmc44.htm.) Van der Waerden, in his book on group theory, reproduced the proof. Dirac uses it in his Dirac (1958). Weyl reproduced the proof in his (Weyl 1930) and (1939) and relied on it throughout the work. This, combined with Schur’s lemma and the double commutant theorem—also given by Schur—were the main results underpinning the group theoretic view.

  15. This material is best given in a modern form in Goodman and Wallach (2009) ch. 9.

  16. For r = 3, there are 3 distinct irreducible representations (there are four if one counts multiplicities.) This corrects French and Rickles (2003) who give the number to be 3! = 6 (p. 218). The mistake is fundamental, for there is a confusion there between permutations (which number 6 for r = 3) and the irreducible representations—and most importantly what the irreducible representations are acting on. This invalidates many of their claims concerning representations.

  17. A signed sum, or signum, means that the sign of the permutation (\(+1\) for a permutation which consists of an even number of inversions of elements, \(-1\) for a permutation which is an odd number of inversions of elements) is the coefficient of the permutation.

  18. Our convention will be to take multiplication on the right for \(\,\mathbb {C}[\mathfrak {S}_{r}]\,\).

  19. Schur’s first formulation of what is now called Schur–Weyl duality appeared in his 1901 doctoral dissertation under Frobenius. Under the impetus of Weyl’s (and other’s) work in quantum mechanics, Schur revisited this topic in 1927, giving a more concise version relying on the double commutant theorem. Weyl was aware of this 1927 paper in writing Weyl (Weyl 1930), and cites it in ch. V note 1. But he does not use it, preferring the 1901 formulation. Weyl (1939) used Schur’s (1927) paper more extensively and there gives the double commutant theorem. He compares the two formulations pp. 96 ff.

  20. Saunders in (2003b) 301, says that ‘one is not thereby led to local symmetry groups (symmetries which, viewed as Lie groups, are infinite dimensional).’ It is not clear what he might mean, as almost all Lie groups which are local symmetry groups are finite dimensional.

  21. If V is irreducible then \(A = \,\mathbb {C}\, \), and so the dim \(V \otimes _{\mathbb {C}[G]} S\) is either 0 or 1. If V is not irreducible then, since it is simple, reduce it and and go back to the first case.

  22. Fulton and Harris (1991) lemma 6.23 and following exercises. The Zariski topology is coarser than the euclidean metric topology.

  23. Here \(\mathbb {C}^{*}\) is \(\mathbb {C} - \{0\}\). The components \(\,\varepsilon _{}\,\) of the eigenvalue sum are determined by N. Weyl interprets them to be energy-values.

  24. For the general partition mentioned before \([3, 2^{2}, 1^{3}]\) it would be (1, 1, 1).

  25. The English translation of this passage and the entire section is misprinted and at variance with the german original, so I have corrected it here. (See Weyl 1931 368 for comparison.) In the two particle case the symmetric space has the eigenvalue \(2 E_{1}\) (\(f_{1}' = f\)) which does not occur in the (lower) antisymmetric space. But \(\textit{E}_{1} + \textit{E}_{2}\) occurs in both (because \(f_{1} = f_{2} = 1\)).

  26. This analogy originated in Schrödinger (1950) and was given currency in Mary Hesse’s (1963, pp. 49–50). It was given a further twist by Dieks and Versteegh (2008), who adapted it to differentiate between fermions and bosons. Dieks (2010) states that this analogy is closer to the QM situation than Black’s two spheres. I agree.

  27. And subsequently over many other publications, for example Krause and Arenhart (2015), de Barros et al. (2019).

  28. I thank an anonymous referee for pointing out this presupposition in the Muller and Saunders paper.

  29. In the same way there seems to have been a convergence of both sides to a “structuralist interpretation” of QM. For some animadversions on structuralism see Heathcote (2014).

  30. This only seems plausible, I believe, because of the exclusive focus on the case where there is only one permutation other than the identity: the two particle case. Further: It is pertinent to ask whether, in all this talk of permuting particles, anyone has thought to wonder how these particles are being moved around by such a dynamical transformation. But surely to ask the question should make it clear that it could not be taken literally.

  31. The minimal dimension for the existence of such indecomposable tensors is four.

  32. It is worth noting in this respect that Einstein et al. (1935) had stated more circumspectly than was acknowledged by their critics that the system in such a complete state is not further analysable: ‘We cannot, however, calculate the state in which either one of the two systems is left after the interaction.’ (p. 779).

  33. Von Neumann also had interests that encompassed philosophy, but it is fair to say that these were more on the side of logic and set theory.

  34. In ch. IV, §9, he says: ‘If two such individuals [that are fully equivalent] unite to form a single physical system \(\textit{I}^{2}\)...’ the vectors will be tensors of order two. Weyl (Weyl 1931 p. 239). This is the basis for the electrons being indistinguishable later in the same section.

  35. See for example the discussion of factorisation of the operator algebras in Murray and von Neumann (1936), ch III. Schrödinger, in his (Schrödinger 1950) does seem to embrace the idea that indistinguishability of electrons means indistinguishable tout court but he offers no argument for this view.

  36. Infinite permutation groups have been studied but not everything will carry over, particularly such things as the trace. For finite groups every representation is equivalent to a unitary representation. But this is not so for an infinite group. This raises the question as to whether our current picture will carry over to an infinite set of particles in a field theory. Whether this pessimism is justified it may be too early to tell. For example see the work of Vershik and Okounkov (2005) and Tsilevich et al. (2019). (For early background see Cameron 1990).

  37. It should be noted in this context that ‘Hilbert space’ is rarely ever mentioned in Weyl (1931). It is an idiosyncrasy of the work.

  38. To the best of my knowledge it has never been explained why this project was left incomplete, but in a letter to Pascual Jordan, dated Dec. 1949 (Rédei 2005) von Neumann indicated that his work Von Neumann (1960) most closely represented his finished thoughts on quantum logic. Von Neumann believed that the ring \(\mathrm {II}_{1}\) was the correct ring in which to do QM and it was also his foremost example of a continuous geometry.

References

  • Akin, K., Buschsbaum, D. A., & Weyman, J. (1982). Schur functors and Schur complexes. Advances in Mathematics, 44, 207–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Artin, E. (1950). The influence of J. H. M. Wedderburn on the development of modern algebra. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 56, 65–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernardi, A., & Vanzo, D. (2018). A new class of non-identifiable skew-symmetric tensors. Annali Di Matematica, 197, 1499–1510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berto, F. (2017). Counting the particles: Entity and identity in the philosophy of physics. Metaphysica, 18(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biedenharn, L. C., & Louck, J. D. (1981). The Racah–Wigner algebra in quantum theory, encyclopedia of mathematics and its applications (Vol. 9). Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Briët, J., Buhrman, H., & Toner, B. A. (2011). Generalized Grothendieck inequality and nonlocal correlations that require high entanglement. Communications in Mathematical Physics, 305, 827–843.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnside, W. (1905). On the condition of reducibility of any group of linear substitutions. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society Series, 2(1), 430–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnside, W. (1911). Theory of groups of finite order (second ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (reprinted by Dover 1951) .

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, P. J. (1990). Oligomorphic permutation groups. London mathematical society lecture notes series 152. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Caulton, A. (2014). Qualitative individuation in permutation-invariant quantum mechanics. Preprint arXiv:1409.0247v1 [quant-ph].

  • Caulton, A. (2013). Discerning “indistinguishable” quantum systems. Philosophy of Science, 80(1), 49–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Barros, J. A., Holik, F., & Krause, D. (2019). Indistinguishability and the origins of contextuality in physics. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A, 377, 20190150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dieks, D. (2010). Are ‘identical quantum particles’ weakly discernible objects. In M. Suarez, M. Dorato, & M. Redei (Eds.), EPSA philosophical issues in the sciences: Launch of the European Philosophy of Science Association (Vol. 2, pp. 21–31). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dieks, D., & Lubberdink, A. (2011). How classical particles emerge from the quantum world. Foundations of Physics, 41, 1051–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dieks, D., & Versteegh, M. A. M. (2008). Identical quantum particles and weak discernibility. Foundations of Physics, 38, 923–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dirac, P. A. M. (1926). On the theory of quantum mechanics. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A, 112, 661–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dirac, P. A. M. (1949). Forms of relativistic dynamics. Reviews of Modern Physics, 21(3), 392–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dirac, P. A. M. (1958). Principles of quantum mechanics (4th ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dixmier, J. (1981). Von Neumann algebras. Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., & Rosen, N. (1935). Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Physical Review, 47, 777–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fano, U., & Racah, G. (1959). Irreducible tensorial sets. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C., & Reeds, J. A. (1994). Bell inequalities, Grothendieck’s constant, and root two. SIAM Journal of Discrete Mathematics, 7(1), 48–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2015). Identity and individuality in quantum physics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (Online). https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qt-idind/.

  • French, S., & Krause, D. (2006). Identity in physics: A historical, philosophical and formal analysis. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Redhead, M. (1988). Quantum physics and the identity of indiscernibles. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39, 233–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Rickles, D. (2003). Understanding permutation symmetry. In K. Brading & E. Castellani (Eds.), Symmetries in physics: Philosophical reflections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frobenius, G., & Schur, I. (1906). Über die Äquivalenz der Gruppen linearer Substitutionen. Sitzungsberichte der Königlich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, VI–VII, 209–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fulton, W. (1997). Young tableaux: With applications to representation theory and geometry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fulton, W., & Harris, J. (1991). Representation theory: A first course. Graduate texts in mathematics (Vol. 129). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi, G. C., & Marinatto, L. (2004). General criterion for the entanglement of two identical particles. Physical Review A, 70(012019), 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, R., & Wallach, N. R. (2009). Symmetry, representations, and invariants. Graduate texts in mathematics (Vol. 255). New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heathcote, A. (2014). On the exhaustion of mathematical entities by structures. Axiomathes, 24(2), 167–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. (1963). Models and analogies in science. London: Sheed and Ward. (reprinted 1966 Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press) .

    Google Scholar 

  • Khinchin, A. Y. (1960). Mathematical foundations of quantum statistics (Trans. Irwin Shapiro, 1951) N.Y. Graylock.

  • Krause, D. (1992). On a quasi-set theory. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 33, 402–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krause, D., & Arenhart, J. R. B. (2015). Is identity really so fundamental? Foundations of Physics, 24, 51–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., & Bigaj, T. (2010). The principle of the identity of indiscernibles and quantum mechanics. Philosophy of Science, 77(1), 117–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lam, T. Y. (1998). A theorem of burnside on matrix rings. The American Mathematical Monthly, 105(7), 651–3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leinaas, J. M., & Myrheim, J. (1977). On the theory of identical particles. II Nuovo Cimento B, 37(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mac Lane, S., & Birkoff, G. (1999). Algebra (3rd ed.). Providence: AMS Chelsea.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackey, G. W. (1951). On induced representations of groups. American Journal of Mathematics, 73(3), 576–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackey, G. W. (1978). Unitary group representations in physics, probability and number theory. Reading, MA: Benjamin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margenau, H. (1944). The exclusion principle and its philosophical importance. Philosophy of Science, 11(4), 187–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Messiah, A. (1962). Quantum mechanics Vol. II (Trans. J. Potter). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

  • Messiah, A., & Greenberg, O. W. (1964). The symmetrization postulate and its experimental foundation. Physical Review, 136, B248–B267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, F. (2011). Withering away, weakly. Synthese, 180, 223–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, F. (2015). The rise of relationals. Mind, 124, 201–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, F., & Saunders, S. (2008). Discerning fermions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59, 499–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, F., & Seevinck, M. (2009). Discerning elementary particles. Philosophy of Science, 76, 179–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, F. J., & von Neumann, J. (1936). On rings of operators. Annals of Mathematics Second Series, 31(1), 116–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radjabalipour, M., Rosenthal, P. R., & Yahagi, B. R. (2004). Burnside’s theorem for matrix rings over division algebras. Linear Algebras and its Applications, 383, 29–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rédei, Miklós. (2005). John von Neumann: Selected letters. History of mathematics (Vol. 27). Providence, RI: London Mathematical Society, American Mathematical Society.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sagan, B. E. (2001). The symmetric group: Representations, combinatorial algorithms, and symmetric functions. Graduate texts in mathematics (2nd ed., Vol. 203). New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, S. (2003b). Physics and Leibniz’s principles. In K. Brading & E. Castellani (Eds.), Symmetries in physics: Philosophical reflections (pp. 289–307). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, S. (2003a). Indiscernibles, general covariance, and other symmetries: The case for non-reductive relationalism. In A. Ashtekar, D. Howard, J. Renn, S. Sarkar, & A. Shimony (Eds.), Revisiting the foundations of relativistic physics: Festschrift in honour of John Stachel. Amsterdam: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, S. (2006). Are quantum particles objects? Analysis, 66, 52–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, S. (2016). The emergence of individuals in physics. In A. Guay & T. Pradeu (Eds.), Individuals across the sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schliemann, J., Ignacio Cirac, I., Kus, M., Lewenstein, M., & Loss, D. (2001). Quantum correlations in two-fermion systems. Physical Review A, 64, 022303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. (1950). What is an elementary particle? Endeavour, 114

  • Schrödinger, E. (1936). Probability relations between separated systems. Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, 32(3), 446–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. (1951). Science and humanism: Physics in our time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schur, I. (1927). Über die rationalen Darstellungen der allgemeinen linearen Gruppe. Sitzungsberichte Akad. Berlin (pp. 58–75).

  • Schur, I. (1905). Neue Begründung der Theorie der Gruppencharaktere. Sitzungsberichte der Königlich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, XVIII, 406–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sternberg, S. (1994). Group theory and physics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toraldo Di Francia, G. (1978). What is a physical object? Scientia, 113, 57–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Towber, J. (1977). Two new functors from modules to algebras. Journal of Algebra, 47, 80–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsilevich, N. V., Vershik, A. M., & Yuzvinsky, S. (2019). The intrinsic hyperplane arrangement in an arbitrary irreducible representation of the symmetric group. arXiv:1910.08302 [math.CO].

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1991). Quantum mechanics: An empiricist view. London: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C., & Peschard, I. (2008). Identity over time: Objectively. Subjectively, Philosophical Quarterly, 58(230), 15–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vershik, A. M., & Okounkov, A. Y. (2005). A new approach to the representation theory of the symmetric groups. II. Journal of Mathematical Sciences, 131, 5471–5494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann, J. (1929). Zur Algebra der Funktionaloperationen und Theorie der normalen Operatoren. Mathematische Annalen, 102, 370–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann, J. (1960). Continuous geometry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann, J. (1961). Collected works Vol. III: Rings of operators (ed. A. H. Taub). Oxford: Pergamon Press.

  • Weyl, H. (1929). Der Zusammenhang Zwischen Der Symmetrischen Und Der Linearen Gruppe. Annals of Mathematics, 30(1), 499–516.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (1930). Gruppentheorie und Quantenmechanik (2nd ed.). Leipzig: S. Hirzel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (1931). The theory of groups and quantum mechanics (trans. by H. P. Robertson of Gruppentheorie und Quantenmechanik, second edition). London: Methuen (reprinted Dover 1950).

  • Weyl, H. (1939). The classical groups. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (1949). Philosophy of mathematics and natural science. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (2009). In P. Pesic (Ed.), Mind and nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Weyman, J. (2003). Cohomology of vector bundles and syzygies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. P. (1959). Group theory and its applications to the quantum mechanics of atomic spectra. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

My thanks to the two anonymous referees; their suggestions have led to numerous improvements.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adrian Heathcote.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Adrian Heathcote has retired from Department of Philosophy, University of Sydney, Sydney, Australia.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Heathcote, A. Multiplicity and indiscernibility. Synthese 198, 8779–8808 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02600-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02600-8

Keywords

Navigation