Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

It’s About Scientific Secrecy, Dummy: A Better Equilibrium Among Genomics Patenting, Scientific Research and Health Care

  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper offers a different pragmatic and patent-based approach to concerns regarding the negative effects of genetic-based patenting on advancing scientific research and providing adequate and accessible health care services. At the basis of this approach lies an explication of a mandatory provisional patented paper procedure (PPPA), designed for genetic-based patents and administered by leading scientific journals in the field, while officially acknowledged by the USPTO, and subsequently by other patent offices as well. It is argued that the uniqueness of PPPAs lies in subsequently mitigating the negative ramifications of genetic patents on scientific research and genetic-based health care services, while basing such mitigation on a patents’ advocate viewpoint that neither discards the patent system nor jeopardizes its integrity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Compare, for example, Caulfield et al. (2000, 2006), Czarnitzki et al. (2009), Fabrizio and Di Minin (2008), Huang and Murray (2008), forthcoming, Walsh et al. (2005b) with Andrews (2002b), Cook-Deegan et al. (2009), Farrelly (2007), Lakhani et al. (2006), Petherbridge (2007), Smith et al. (2004).

  2. A patent pool is a consortium of at least two companies agreeing to cross-license patents relating to a particular technology. The creation of a patent pool can save patentees and licensees time and money, and, in case of blocking patents, it may also be the only reasonable method for making the invention available to the public.

  3. “Prior art” constitutes all information that has been made available to the public in any form before a given date that might be relevant to a patent's claims of originality. If an invention has been described in prior art, a patent on that invention is not valid. With respect to the experimental use clause, section 102(b) of the patent statute provides that a patent may be obtained unless "the invention was…in public use or on sale in this country, more than 1 year prior to the date for application for patent in the United States." Public use may not mean commercial use, but commercial use is typically considered public use. An invention is considered on sale if it is sold or offered for sale. However, the doctrine of experimental use allows an inventor, or others cooperating with the inventor, to engage in activities that would otherwise fall under the public use or on-sale bars, provided that the use or sale is incidental to experimentation. By showing that the activity falls within the limits of experimental use, it is possible to refute a charge that the activity in question rendered the invention unpatentable.

  4. This belief is the basis of the Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS Agreement). See e.g. WTO (1994).

  5. As indicated in: (35 United States Code, §112, 113; Walsh et al. 2005a; Eisenberg 1987).

  6. For a definition of “prior art” see footnote no. 4 above.

  7. Compare the 12-month period in the US, with the 6-month period granted only to the patent applicantee in Japan, and the non-existing grace period under the regulations of the European patent office (EPO). See: (35 United States Code, §102(b); European Patent Convention, no. 54; Tokkyo Ho [Japanese patent act], §30(1), 30(3)).

  8. More details about this lawsuit and the professional organizations standing behind it can be found at: http://www.aclu.org/freespeech/gen/brca.html.

  9. This is also true, apparently, with respect to EPO (Gugerell 1994, 104–107).

  10. See also: http://www.uspto.gov/web/offices/pac/provapp.htm.

  11. Ibid.

  12. Ibid.

  13. For a fuller description of the “prisoner’s dilemma” see Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy at: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/prisoner-dilemma.

  14. For a more extensive list see: (Zemer 2005, 893–894 [note no.1]).

  15. The “sufficiency proviso” (also referred to as the “Lockean proviso”) is encompassed in Locke’s assertion that the fruits of labor is the laborer’s private property “at least where there is enough, and as good left in common for others” (Locke 1967, II, §27). As to the contrast(s) between left and right libertarians regarding this proviso, see for example: Fried (2004).

  16. Even those who are criticizing Locke’s labor theory concede its central role in his property-rights theory. For instance, Wendy Gordon’s critique of the manner by which Locke’s labor theory is used in order to justify existing copyright laws in the U.S. precisely stems from acknowledging the primary role of his labor theory in basing these copyright laws. In Gordon words: “Given that versions of labor theory are so often touted as support fro giving creators strong intellectual property rights, Lockean theory deserves closer examination than the intellectual property courts have given it so far” (Gordon 1993, 1540). See also (Zemer 2005, 912–918) for further discussion. A notable exception to the rule, though, is probably Robert Nozick’s stance. Advocating Locke’s property right theory through a right-libertarian lenses, he criticizes the logic of Locke’s labor theory while presenting it as a superfluous portion of Locke’s overall property rights philosophy (Nozick 1974, 174–175). However, as already observed by some commentators, “belittling” Locke’s labor theory stems from Nozick’s inability to accept the more complicated nature of Locke’s philosophy since such an acceptance undermines Nozick’s right-libertarian viewpoint (Hailwood 1996, 38–48; Wolff 1991, 102–116).

  17. Notice, in this respect, that claiming this result could have been achieved through appealing to the “exemption for research” clause is problematic because this clause can be used only in cases where the research using the patented knowledge is completely detached from any commercial endeavors.

  18. http://grants.nih.gov/grants/policy/nihgps_2003/NIHGPS_Part7.htm; http://publicaccess.nih.gov/policy.htm.

  19. Such services are already available commercially, for example: http://web.guardtime.com/?page_id=3; http://www.digistamp.com; https://digitalid.verisign.Com/client/help/id_intro.htm#time_stamp.

  20. By using available DTS toolkits in the online submission software, as these toolkits are designed to be embedded within a third-party software environment. See: http://web.guardtime.com/?page_id=29; http://www.digistamp.com/apiover.htm.

References

  • Andrews, L. B. (2002a). The gene patent dilemma: Balancing commerical incentives with health needs. Houston Journal of Health Law & Policy, 2, 65–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, L. B. (2002b). Genes and patent policy: Rethinking intellectual property rights. Nature Reviews Genetics, 3(10), 803–808.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, F. (2002). Integrating genomics technologies in health care: Practice and policy challenges and opportunities. Physiological Genomics, 8(1), 33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod, R. (1980). Effective choice in the prisoner’s dilemma. The Journal of Conflict Resolution, 24(1), 3–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod, R. (1981). The emergence of cooperation among egoists. American Political Science Review, 75(2), 306–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod, R., & Hamilton, W. D. (1981). The emergence of cooperation. Science, 211, 1390–1396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bagley, M. A. (2006). Academic discourse and propriety rights: Putting patents in their proper place. Boston College Law Review, 47(2), 217–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benowitz, S. (2002). French challenge to BRCA1 patent underlies European discontent. Journal of National Cancer Institute, 94, 80–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bentwich, I., Avniel, A., Karov, Y., Aharonov, R., Gilad, S., Barad, O., et al. (2005). Identification of hundreds of conserved and nonconserved human microRNAs. Nature Genetics, 37(7), 766–770.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blumenthal, D., Campbell, E. G., Anderson, M. S., Causino, N., & Louis, K. S. (1997). Withholding research results in academic life science. Evidence from a national survey of faculty. JAMA, 277(15), 1224–1228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borger, J. (1999). Rush to patent genes stalls cures for disease. Guardian (London), 1.

  • Brenner v. Manson. (1996). 383 U.S., 519,534.

  • Brock, G. (1995). Is redistribution to help the needy just? Analysis, 55, 50–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brody, B. (2000). Redistribution without egalitarianism. In P. Vallentyne & H. Steiner (Eds.), Left-libertarianism and its critics: The contemporary debate. New York: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A. (1981). Deriving welfare rights from libertarian rights. In P. Brown, C. Johnson, & P. Vernier (Eds.), Income support: Conceptual and policy issues. Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, E. G., Clarridge, B. R., Gokhale, M., Birenbaum, L., Hilgartner, S., Holtzman, N. A., et al. (2002). Data withholding in academic genetics evidence from a national survey. JAMA: American Medical Association.

  • Caulfield, T., Cook-Deegan, R. M., Kieff, F. S., & Walsh, J. P. (2006). Evidence and anecdotes: An analysis of human gene patenting controversies. Nature Biotechnology, 24, 1091–1094.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caulfield, T., Gold, E. R., & Cho, M. K. (2000). Patenting human genetic material: Refocusing the debate. Nature Reviews Genetics, 1(3), 227–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cipra, B. (1993). Electronic time-stamping: The notary public goes digital. Science, 261(5118), 162–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cook-Deegan, R., Chandrasekharan, S., & Angrist, M. (2009). The dangers of diagnostic monopolies. Nature, 458(7237), 405–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, J. M., & Velculescu, V. E. (2006). Implications of micro-RNA profiling for cancer diagnosis. Oncogene, 25(46), 6220–6227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Czarnitzki, D., Glanzel, W., & Hussinger, K. (2009). Heterogeneity of patenting activity and its implications for scientific research. Research Policy, 38(1), 26–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damstedt, B. G. (2002). Limiting locke: A natural law justification for the fair use doctrine. Yale Law Journal, 112, 1179–1221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (2006). Equity and population health: Toward a broader bioethics agenda. Hastings Center Report, pp. 22–35.

  • David, P. A. (2004). Can “Open Science” be protected from the evolving regime of IPR protections? Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 160(1), 9–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond-v.-Chakrabarty. (1980). 447 U.S.

  • DiMasi, J. A., & Grabowski, H. G. (2007). Should the patent system for new medicines be abolished? Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics, 82(5), 488–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorsett, Y., & Tuschl, T. (2004). siRNAs: Applications in functional genomics and potential as therapeutics. Nature Reviews Drug Discovery, 3(4), 318–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dykxhoorn, D. M., & Lieberman, J. (2004). The silent revolution: RNA interference as basic biology, research tool, and therapeutic. Annual Reviews of Medicine, 56, 401–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ebersole, T. J., Guthrie, M. N., & Goldstein, J. A. (2005). Patent pools as a solution to the licensing problems of diagnostic genetics. Intellectual Property and Technology Law Journal, 17(1), 6–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberg, R. S. (1987). Proprietary rights and the norms of science in biotechnology research. Yale Law Journal, 97(2), 177–231 [225].

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberg, R. S. (2006). Patents and data-sharing in public science. Ind Corp Change, 15(6), 1013–1031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fabrizio, K. R., & Di Minin, A. (2008). Commercializing the laboratory: Faculty patenting and the open science environment. Research Policy, 37(5), 914–931.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farrelly, C. (2007). Gene patents and justice. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 41(2), 147–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fed. Cir. (1996). Vitronics Corp v. Conceptronic Inc., 90 F3d 1576, 1583.

  • Federal Register. (2008). 73(158), 47535, 47540.

  • Feng, H., & Wah, C. C. (2002). Private key generation from on-line handwritten signatures. Information Management & Computer Security, 10(4), 159–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franzoni, C., & Scellato, G. (2008). Estimating the determinants of the patent-publication lags in Europe and USA. Proceedings of Academy of Innovation and Entrepreneurship, 2008, 388–401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fried, B. H. (2004). Left libertarianism: A review essay. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 32(1), 66–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fried, B. H., & Quadrangle, C. (2004). Left libertarianism: A review essay. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 32(1).

  • Fromer, J. C. (2009). Patent disclosure. Iowa Law Review, 94(2), 539–606.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gold, E. R. (2003). SARS genome patent: Symptom or disease? The Lancet, 361(9374), 2002–2003.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gold, R., Caulfield, T. A., & Ray, P. N. (2002). Gene patents and the standard of care. Canadian Medical Association Journal.

  • Gold, E. R., & Danial, K. L. (2003). Balancing trade in patents. Journal of World Intellectual Property, 6(1), 5–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, W. J. (1993). Property right in self-expression: equality and individualism in the natural law of intellectual property, A. Yale LJ, 102(7), 1533–1610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, W. J. (2004). Render copyright unto Caesar: On taking incentives seriously. The University of Chicago Law Review, 71, 75–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grushcow, J. M. (2004). Measuring secrecy: A cost of the patent system revealed. The Journal of Legal Studies, 33(1), 59–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gugerell, C. (1994). The current practice of the European Patent Office. In Paper read at Council of Europe, Ethics and Human Genetics: Proceedings of the 2nd Symposium of the Council of Europe on Bioethics, at Strasbourg.

  • Haber, S., & Stornetta, W. S. (1991). How to time-stamp a digital document. Journal of Cryptology, 3(2), 99–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hailwood, S. A. (1996). Exploring Nozick: Beyond anarchy, state and utopia (38–48 ed.). Aldershot: Avebury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammond, S. M. (2006). MicroRNA therapeutics: A new niche for antisense nucleic acids. Trends in Molecular Medicine, 12(3), 99–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, M. J. (1999). Biotechnology and commodification within health care. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 24(3), 267–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. A., & Eisenberg, R. S. (1998). Can patents deter innovation? The anticommons in biomedical research. Science, 280(5364), 698–701.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ho, M. W. (2001). Why biotech patents are patently absurd: A scientific briefing on TRIPS and related issues. Third World Network.

  • Hodges, D. (2001). U.S. Firm flexes its muscle over CA testing. Medical Post

  • Hoedemaekers, R. (2001a). Commercialization, patents and moral assessment of biotechnology products. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 26(3), 273–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoedemaekers, R. (2001b). Human gene patents: Core issues in a multi-layered debate. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 4(2), 211–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, K. G., & Murray, F. E. (2008). Does patent strategy shape the long-run supply of public knowledge? Evidence from human genetics. Academy of Management Journal (forthcoming).

  • Hughes, J. (1988). Philosophy of intellectual property. The Georgetown Law Journal, 77, 287–366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, R. D. (2007). Gene patents and genetic testing in the United States. Nature Biotechnology, 25(9), 989–990.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, M. H. (1997). John Locke and the origins of private property. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakhani, K. R., Jeppesen, L. B., Lohse, P. A., & Panetta, J. A. (2006). The value of openness in scientific problem solving.

  • Locke, J. (1967). Two treatises of government. In P. Lasslet (Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Long, P. (2002). Patent signals. University of Chicago Law Review, 69(2), 625–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, J., & Hubbard, T. (2007). The big idea: Prizes to stimulate R&D for new medicines. Chicago-Kent Law Review, 82(3), 1520–1554.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lu, J., Getz, G., Miska, E. A., Alvarez-Saavedra, E., Lamb, J., Peck, D., et al. (2005). MicroRNA expression profiles classify human cancers. Nature, 435(7043), 834–838.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macer, D. R. J. (2002). Patent or perish? An ethical approach to patenting human genes and proteins. The Pharmacogenomics Journal, 2(6), 361–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machan, T. R. (1997). Does libertarianism imply the welfare state? Res Publica, 3, 131–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merrill, S. A., Levin, R. C., & Myers, M. B. (2004). A patent system for the 21st century. National Academies Press.

  • Merz, J. F., & Cho, M. K. (2005). What are gene patents and why are people worried about them? Community Genetics, 8(4), 203–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merz, J. F., Cho, M. K., Robertson, M. J., & Leonard, D. G. B. (1997). Disease gene patenting is a bad innovation. Molecular Diagnosis, 2(4), 299–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merz, J. F., Kriss, A. G., Leonard, D. G. B., & Cho, M. K. (2002). Diagnostic testing fails the test: The pitfalls of patents are illustrated by the case of haemochromatosis. Nature, 415, 577–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, A. D. (2004). Intellectual property and information control: philosophic foundations and contemporary issues. Transaction Pub.

  • Murray, F., & Stern, S. (2007). Do formal intellectual property rights hinder the free flow of scientific knowledge? An empirical test of the anti-commons hypothesis. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 63(4), 648–687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Narveson, J. (1992). Libertarianism, postlibertarianism, and the welfarre state: Reply to Friedman. Critical Review, 6(1), 45–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Narveson, J. (1995). Contracting for liberty. In T. R. Machan (Ed.), Liberty for the twenty-first century: Contemporary libertarian thought. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • National-Academy-of-Sciences. (2005). Reaping the benefits of genomic and proteomic research: Intellectual property rights, innovation, and public health. Washington, DC: National Academies Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state and utopia. New York: Basic Books Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Otsuka, M. (2000). Self-ownership and equality: A Lockean reconciliation. In P. Vallentyne & H. Steiner (Eds.), Left-libertarianism and its critics: The contemporary debate. New York: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papaioannou, T. (2008). Human gene patents and the question of liberal morality. Genomics, Society and Policy.

  • Paradise, J., Andrews, L., & Holbrook, T. (2005). Intellectual property: Patents on human genes: An analysis of scope and claims. Science, 307(5715), 1566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peres, J. (1999). Genetic tests reduce neighborhood’s grief: Screening stops unsise matches. Chicago Tribune, 16.

  • Petherbridge, L. (2007). Road map to revolution-patent-based open science. Maine Law Review, 59(2), 339–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, T. W. (2005). Human rights and global health: A research program. Metaphilosophy, 36(1 2), 182–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poste, G., Roberts, D., & Gentry, S. (1997). Patents, ethics and improving healthcare. Bulletin of Medical Ethics, 124, 29–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pottage, A. (2007). The socio-legal implications of the new biotechnologies. Law and Social Science, 3, 321–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rapoport, A. (1974). Prisoner’s dilemma: Recollections and observations. In A. Rapoport (Ed.), Game theory as a theory of conflict resolution. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, M. J. (1997). Is it right to patent DNA? Bulletin of Medical Ethics, 124, 21–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, J., Mulligan, L., & Graham, J. K. (1981). Property and people: Political usages of Locke and some contemporaries. Journal of the History of Ideas, 42, 29–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, G. A. J. (1994). Locke’s philosophy: Content and context. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roin, B. N. (2009). Unpatentable drugs and the standards of patentability. Texas Law Review, 87(3), 503–570.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schatz, U. (1997). Biotechnology, patents and morality. In S. Sterckx (Ed.), Biotechnology, patents and morality. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schissel, A., Merz, J. F., & Cho, M. K. (1999). Survey confirms fears about licensing of genetic tests. Nature, 402(6758), 118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sevilla, C., Julian-Reynier, C., Eisinger, F., Stoppa-Lyonnet, D., Bressac-de Paillerets, B., Sobol, H., et al. (2003). Impact of gene patents on the cost-effective delivery of care: The case of BRCA1 genetic testing. International Journal of Technology Assessment in Health Care, 19(02), 287–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, C. (2001). Navigating the patent thicket: Cross licenses, patent pools and standard settings. In A. B. Jaffe, J. Lerner, & C. Stern (Eds.), Innovation policy and the economy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skevington, P. J., & Hart, T. P. (1997). Trusted third parties in electronic commerce. BT Technology Journal, 15(2), 39–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, R. D., Thorsteindottir, H., Daar, A. S., Gold, E. R., & Singer, P. A. (2004). Genomics knowledge and equity: A global public goods perspective of the patent system. Bulletin of the World Health Organization, 82, 385–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterba, J. P. (1994). From liberty to welfare. Ethics, 105(1), 64–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterba, J. P. (2000). From liberty to welfare: An update. Social Theory and Practice, 26(3), 465–478.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz, J. E. (2006). Scrooge and intellectual property rights. British Medical Journal, 333(7582), 1279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stott, M., & Valentine, J. (2004). Gene patenting and medical research: A view from a pharmaceutical company. Nature Reviews Drug Discovery, 3(4), 364–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Svatos, M. (1996). Biotechnology and the utilitarian argument for patents. Social Philosophy & Policy, 13(2), 113–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Svatos, M. (1997). Biotechnology, patents and morality: A philosophical commentary on the conference. In S. Sterckx (Ed.), Biotechnology, patents and morality. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tananbaum, G., & Holmes, L. (2008). The evolution of web-based peer-review systems. Learned Publishing, 21(4), 300–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Parijs, P. (1995). Real freedom for all. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walpole, I. R., Dawkins, H. J. S., Sinden, P. D., & Leary, P. C. O. (2003). Human gene patents: The possible impacts on genetic services healthcare. Medical Journal of Australia, 179(4), 203–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, J. P., Cho, C., & Cohen, W. M. (2005a) Science and law: View from the Bench: Patents and material transfers. Science.

  • Walsh, J. P., Cho, C., & Cohen, W. M. (2005b). Science and the law. Nature.

  • Ware, M. (2005). Online submissionand peer-review systems. Learned Publishing, 18(4), 245–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams-Jones, B. (2002). History of a gene patent: Tracing the development and application of commercial BRCA testing. Health Law Journal, 10, 123–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Willison, D. J., & MacLeod, S. M. (2002). Patenting of genetic material: Are the benefits to society being realized? Canadian Medical Association Journal.

  • Wolff, J. (1991). Robert Nozick: Property, justice and the minimal state. Oxford: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, D. (2001). Reviews. Learned Publishing, 14(2), 151–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • WTO. (1994). Agreement on trade-related aspects of intellectual property rights. In Marrakeslt Agreement Establishing the World Trade Organization, Annex 1C Legal InstrumentsResults of the Uruguay Round.

  • Zemer, L. (2005). Making of a new copyright Lockean. The Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy, 29, 891–947.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Miriam Bentwich.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Bentwich, M. It’s About Scientific Secrecy, Dummy: A Better Equilibrium Among Genomics Patenting, Scientific Research and Health Care. Sci Eng Ethics 18, 263–284 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-011-9257-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-011-9257-3

Keywords

Navigation