Skip to main content
Log in

Prospective Technology Assessment of Synthetic Biology: Fundamental and Propaedeutic Reflections in Order to Enable an Early Assessment

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Synthetic biology is regarded as one of the key technosciences of the future. The goal of this paper is to present some fundamental considerations to enable procedures of a technology assessment (TA) of synthetic biology. To accomplish such an early “upstream” assessment of a not yet fully developed technology, a special type of TA will be considered: Prospective TA (ProTA). At the center of ProTA are the analysis and the framing of “synthetic biology,” including a characterization and assessment of the technological core. The thesis is that if there is any differentia specifica giving substance to the umbrella term “synthetic biology,” it is the idea of harnessing self-organization for engineering purposes. To underline that we are likely experiencing an epochal break in the ontology of technoscientific systems, this new type of technology is called “late-modern technology.” —I start this paper by analyzing the three most common visions of synthetic biology. Then I argue that one particular vision deserves more attention because it underlies the others: the vision of self-organization. I discuss the inherent limits of this new type of late-modern technology in the attempt to control and monitor possible risk issues. I refer to Hans Jonas’ ethics and his early anticipation of the risks of a novel type of technology. I end by drawing conclusions for the approach of ProTA towards an early societal shaping of synthetic biology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. ProTA shares the earliness approach with Vision Assessment (Grin and Grunwald 2000), Real Time TA (Guston and Sarewitz 2002), Technology Characterization (Gleich et al. 2012; Giese et al. 2015), and hermeneutic TA (Grunwald 2012); however, it complements and extends these concepts.

  2. In applying the four orientations, ProTA complements the broad variety of existing TA (and related) studies on synthetic biology. To mention just a few: European Commission (2005), Miller and Selgelid (2006), de Vriend (2006), Royal Academy of Engineering (2009), European Technology Assessment Group (ETAG) (2009), Schmidt (2009), Schmidt et al. (2009), Giese et al. (2015), and others.

  3. On the one hand, “synthetic biology” seems to be a fairly young term. It was (re-)introduced and presented by Eric Kool in 2000 at the annual meeting of the American Chemical Society. Since then, the term has gone on to enjoy a remarkable career and general circulation in the scientific communities as well as in science, technology, and innovation politics. On the other hand, the notion of synthetic biology emerged about 100 years ago—although it was rarely mentioned until 2000. It seems more appropriate to consider the more recent understandings of synthetic biology.

  4. The European Technology Assessment Group (ETAG) (2009) uses the term “paradigm” and states that synthetic biology can be considered a “new research paradigm.” See also Schmidt and de Lorenzo (2012).

  5. Nersessian (2012) has investigated the role of engineering concepts in biology and bioengineering, and in particular the concept formation, sense making, and model-based reasoning in problem-oriented sciences. Engineering practice in biology is rather old; however, its explicit perception and acknowledgement seem to be rather new. A similar point can be made regarding the term “synthetic biology.”

  6. Here, interestingly, a kind of Aristotelian understanding of “nature” seems to be present.

  7. For example, the theories and logic of the emerging technosciences (in a wider sense: “epistemology”).

  8. Ray Kurzweil (2005, 265) argues from another perspective: “We already have a set of powerful tools that emerged from AI research and that have been refined and improved over several decades of development. The brain reverse engineering project will greatly augment this toolkit by also providing a panoply of new, biologically inspired, self-organizing techniques.”

  9. And the European Technology Assessment Group (ETAG) (2009) goes on to stress: “Central in their ideas is the concept of self-regulation, self-organization and feedback as essential characteristics of cognitive systems since continuous adaption to the environment is the only way for living systems to survive.”

  10. My translation from German (J.C.S.).

  11. The limited availability (of the systems) becomes more apparent the deeper the technological approach goes. One could say in a more provocative manner that the more late-modern societies, facilitated by (the ideals of) synthetic biologists, seem to control the material world, the more they lose their ability to control it. A control dialectic is present, as Kastenhofer and Schmidt (2011) show.

  12. Therefore, concerns can be raised as to whether “synthetic biology will enable the design of ‘biological systems’ in a rational and systematic way,” as the EU-NEST High-Level Expert Group on emerging technologies claims (European Commission 2005, 5).

  13. The argumentation of Jonas’ ethics is reconstructed in Schmidt (2013).

  14. For an in-depth treatment, analytic clarification, and stimulating discussion of the precautionary principle see Morris (2000), Sandin (1999) and Manson (2002).

  15. This statement holds although it should be obvious that the biological evolution and the development of humans are also based on instabilities; instabilities are the necessary condition for self-organization, evolution, and development.

  16. In formal terms, Jonas is guided by Kant and takes into account the unconditional obligatory quality of duty with the generalizability of his claim. But, unlike Kant, Jonas fills his imperative with material content referring to the future possibility of being. Moreover, Jonas’ imperative, unlike Kant’s, possesses little internally logical stringency (cf. ibid., 11). After all, it may still be logically feasible to will the present good while sacrificing the future good.

  17. Jonas did this explicitly in a book chapter (“Laßt uns einen Menschen klonieren: Von der Eugenik zur Gentechnologie”, in the book “Technik, Medizin und Ethik“, 1985) that has only been published in German.

  18. The new “collaborative kind of technology” seems to be closer to humans and to their actions and self-perceptions; it is not alien to humans like the mechanical type of technology of classic-modern engineering. From the same perspective, and a few decades earlier, the Marxist philosopher Ernst Bloch coined the term “alliance technology” to underline the difference between mechanical and biology-based technology (Bloch 1995). According to Bloch, we may call a technology based on self-organization “alliance technology.” Today, however, beyond Bloch’s thoughts, we need to consider the high ambivalence of this type of technology.

  19. Jonas had this in mind when he formulated his precautionary principle. Jonas believed that we should stick to classic-modern technology. His conception of adequate technology is therefore, in some respects, very similar to what Endy (2005) advocates.

  20. Dupuy states: “The unpredictable behavior […] means that engineers will not know how to make [… these] machines until they actually start building them” (Dupuy 2004, 18). The famous physicist Richard Feynman is quoted as saying: “What I cannot create, I do not understand” (cf. Schwille and Diez 2009, 223).

  21. In line with these concerns, Bill Joy warns about the dangers of the well-known and highly disputed dystopia: the “gray goo” (Joy 2000).

  22. In Gleich et al. (2012) the “systems type of synthetic biology” is analyzed and assessed in more detail.

  23. This is in line with Nordmann’s concerns as to whether we can cope with this kind of technology (cf. Nordmann 2005, 2008). His objections are far-reaching: “This is a critique no longer of what we do to nature in the name of social and economic control. Instead it is a critique of what we do to ourselves as we surrender control to pervasive technical systems” (Nordmann 2008, 182).

References

  • Action Group on Erosion, Technology and Concentration (2007). Extreme genetic engineering: An introduction to synthetic biology. http://www.etcgroup.org/en/materials/publications.html?pub_id=602. Accessed 23 May 2013.

  • Bloch, E. (1995). The principle of hope. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Csete, M. E., & Doyle, J. C. (2002). Reverse engineering of biological complexity. Science, 295, 1664–1669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Vriend, H. C. (2006). Constructing life: Early social reflections on the emerging field of synthetic biology (Working Document 9). The Hague: Rathenau Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deplazes, A., & Huppenbauer, M. (2009). Synthetic organisms and living machines: Positioning the products of synthetic biology at the borderline between living and nonliving matter. Systems and Synthetic Biology, 3, 55–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DFG, acatech, and Leopoldina (2009). Synthetische Biologie. Stellungnahme. Bonn: Wiley-VCH.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drexler, K. E. (1990). Engines of creation: The coming era of nanotechnology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drubin, D. A., Way, J. C., & Silver, P. A. (2007). Designing biological systems. Genes and Development, 21, 242–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupuy, J.-P. (2004). Complexity and Uncertainty: A Prudential Approach to Nanotechnology. Brussels: European Commission. www.europa.eu.int/comm/health/ph_risk/documents/ev_20040301_en.pdf. Accessed 21 Nov 2012.

  • Dupuy, J.-P., & Grinbaum, A. (2006). Living with uncertainty: Toward the ongoing normative assessment of nanotechnology. In D. Baird & J. Schummer (Eds.), Nanotechnology challenges: Implications of philosophy, ethics and society (pp. 287–314). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ebeling, W., & Feistel, R. (1994). Chaos und Kosmos. Prinzipien der Evolution. Heidelberg/Berlin: Spektrum Akademischer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Endy, D. (2005). Foundations for engineering biology. Nature, 438, 449–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • European Commission (2005). Synthetic biology. Applying engineering to biology (Report of a NEST-High Level Expert Group EU 21796). Brussels: European Commission.

  • European Technology Assessment Group (ETAG) (2009). Making a perfect life. Bioengineering in the 21st century. The Hague: Rathenau Institute.

  • Gibson, D. G., et al. (2010). Creation of a bacterial cell controlled by a chemically synthesized genome. Science, 329, 52–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giese, B., et al. (2013). Rational engineering principles in synthetic biology: A framework for quantitative analysis and an initial assessment. Biological Theory, 8, 324–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giese, B., et al. (Eds.). (2015). Synthetic biology: Character and impact. Berlin/New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gleich, A. V., Giese, B., Königstein, S., & Schmidt, J. C. (2012). Synthetische Biologie: Revolution oder Evolution? Definition, Charakterisierung und Entwicklungsperspektiven der Synthetischen Biologie mit Fokus auf den damit verbundenen Chancen und Risiken. Bremen: afortec.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grin, J., & Grunwald, A. (Eds.). (2000). Vision assessment. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grunwald, A. (2012). Synthetische Biologie als Naturwissenschaft mit technischer Ausrichtung. Plädoyer für eine “Hermeneutische Technikfolgenabschätzung”. Technikfolgenabschätzung, Theorie und Praxis, 21(2), 10–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guston, D. H., & Sarewitz, D. (2002). Real-time Technology Assessment. Technology in Society, 24(1/2), 93–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heylighen, F. (2002). The science of self-organization and adaptivity. Brussels: Center Leo Apostel/Free University of Brussels.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubig, C. (2006). Die Kunst des Möglichen I. Technikphilosophie als Reflexion der Medialität. Bielefeld: transcript.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life. Towards a philosophical biology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1984). The imperative of responsibility: In search of an ethics for the technological age. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1985). Laßt uns einen Menschen klonieren: Von der Eugenik zur Gentechnologie. In H. Jonas (Ed.), Technik, Medizin und Ethik (pp. 162–203). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, R. (2004). Soft machines. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joy, B. (2000). Why the future doesn’t need us? Our most powerful 21st-century technologies—robotics, genetic engineering, and nanotech—are threatening to make humans an endangered species. Wired, 8.04, 238–262. www.wired.com/wired/archive/8.04/joy_pr.html. Accessed 18 February 2014.

  • Kastenhofer, K., & Schmidt, J. C. (2011). On intervention, construction and creation: Power and knowledge in technoscience and late-modern technology. In T. B. Zülsdorfer, et al. (Eds.), Quantum engagements: Social reflections of nanoscience and emerging technologies (pp. 177–194). Heidelberg: Akademische Verlagsgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köchy, K. (2011). Konstruktion von Leben? Herstellungsideale und Machbarkeitsgrenzen in der Synthetischen Biologie. In V. Gerhardt, et al. (Eds.), Evolution. Theorie, Formen und Konsequenzen eines Paradigmas in Natur, Technik und Kultur (pp. 233–242). Heidelberg: Akademie Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Küppers, B. O. (2000). Die Strukturwissenschaften als Bindeglied zwischen Natur- und Geisteswissenschaften. In B. O. Küppers (Ed.), Die Einheit der Wirklichkeit. Zum Wissenschaftsverständnis der Gegenwart (pp. 89–110). München: Fink.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurzweil, R. (2005). The singularity is near: When humans transcend biology. New York: Penguin Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langer, J. S. (1980). Instabilities and pattern formation. Review Modern Physics, 52, 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liebert, W., & Schmidt, J. C. (2010). Towards a prospective technology assessment: challenges and requirements for technology assessment in the age of technoscience. Poiesis and Praxis, 7, 99–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N. (2003). Soziologie des Risikos. Berlin/New York: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luisi, P. L., & Stano, P. (2011). Minimal cell mimicry. Nature Chemistry, 3, 755–756.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mainzer, K. (1996). Thinking in complexity: The complex dynamics of matter, mind, and mankind. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Manson, N. A. (2002). Formulating the precautionary principle. Environmental Ethics, 24(3), 263–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marliere, P. (2009). The farther, the safer: A manifesto for securely navigating synthetic species away from the old living world. Systems and Synthetic Biology, 3, 77–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, S., & Selgelid, M. (2006). Ethical and philosophical consideration of the dual-use dilemma in the biological sciences. Australian National University, Canberra/Australia: Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, J. (Ed.). (2000). Rethinking risk and the precautionary principle. Woburn/Mass.: Butterworth-Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. J. (2012). Engineering concepts: The interplay between concept formation and modeling practices in bioengineering sciences. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 19(3), 222–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicolis, G., & Prigogine, I. (1977). Self-organization in nonequilibrium systems: From dissipative structures to order through fluctuations. New York/London: J. Wiley and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nolfi, S., & Floreano, D. (2000). Evolutionary Robotics: The Biology, Intelligence, and Technology of Self-Organizing Machines. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nordmann, A. (2005). Noumenal technology: Reflection on the incredible tininess of nano. Techné, 8(3), 3–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nordmann, A. (2008). Technology Naturalized. A Challenge to Design for the Human Scale. In P. E. Vermaas, et al. (Eds.), Philosophy and design (pp. 173–184). Heidelberg/New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pottage, A., & Sherman, B. (2007). Organisms and manufactures: On the history of plant inventions. Melb. Univ. Law Rev., 31, 539–568.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pühler, A., et al. (Eds.). (2011). Synthetische Biologie. Die Geburt einer neuen Technikwissenschaft. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roco, M. C., & Bainbridge, W. S. (Eds.). (2002). Converging technologies for improving human performance. Arlington: National Science Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Royal Academy of Engineering (2009). Synthetic biology: Scope, applications and implications. London: Royal Academy of Engineering.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandin, P. (1999). Dimensions of the precautionary principle. Human and Ecological Risk Assessment, 5(5), 889–907.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, J. C. (2004). Unbounded technologies: Working through the technological reductionism of nanotechnology. In D. Baird, A. Nordmann, & J. Schummer (Eds.), Discovering the Nanoscale (pp. 35–50). Amsterdam: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, J. C. (2008a). Instabilität in Natur und Wissenschaft. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, J. C. (2008b). Towards a philosophy of interdisciplinarity. An attempt to provide a classification and clarification. Poiesis and Praxis, 5(1), 53–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, J. C. (2010). Emergence. In D. Guston (Ed.), Encyclopedia of nanoscience and society (pp. 180–184). London: Sage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, J. C. (2011). Challenged by instability and complexity. On the methodological discussion of mathematical models in nonlinear sciences and complexity theory. In C. Hooker (Ed.), Philosophy of complex systems (pp. 223–254). Amsterdam/Boston: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, J. C. (2013). Defending Hans Jonas’ environmental ethics: On the relation between philosophy of nature and ethics. Environmental Ethics, 35(4), 461–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, M. (2009). Do I understand what I can create? Biosafety issues in synthetic biology. In M. Schmidt, et al. (Eds.), Synthetic biology (pp. 81–100). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, M. (2012). Synthetic biology: Industrial and environmental applications. Weinheim: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, M., & de Lorenzo, V. (2012). Synthetic constructs in/for the environment: Managing the interplay between natural and engineered biology. Federation of European. Biochemical. Societies. Letters, 586, 2199–2206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, M., et al. (Eds.). (2009). Synthetic biology. The technoscience and its societal consequences. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwille, P. (2011). Bottom-up synthetic biology: engineering in a tinkerer’s world. Science, 333, 1252–1254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwille, P., & Diez, S. (2009). Synthetic biology of minimal systems. Critical reviews in biochemistry and molecular biology, 44(4), 223–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • TESSY. (2008). Information leaflet: Synthetic biology in Europe. http://www.tessy-europe.eu/public_docs/SyntheticBiology_TESSY-Information-Leaflet.pdf. Accessed 23 May 2013.

  • Tucker, J. B., & Zilinskas, R. A. (2006). The promise and perlis of synthetic biology. New Atlantis, 12, 25–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Venter, C. (2010). The Creation of ‘Synthia’. Synthetic Life; Science Interview 23rd May 2010, the Naked Scientists. http://www.thenakedscientists.com/html/content/interviews/interview/1332/. Accessed 20 June 2013.

  • von Weizsäcker, C. F. (1974). Die Einheit der Natur. München: Deutscher Taschenbuchverlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiener, N. (1968). Kybernetik. Regelung und Nachrichtenübertragung in Lebewesen und Maschine. Hamburg: Rowohlt.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author gratefully acknowledges two anonymous referees and the editor, and also Bernd Giese (University of Bremen, Germany) and Wolfgang Liebert (University of Natural Resources and Applied Life Sciences, Vienna, Austria) for their very helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jan Cornelius Schmidt.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schmidt, J.C. Prospective Technology Assessment of Synthetic Biology: Fundamental and Propaedeutic Reflections in Order to Enable an Early Assessment. Sci Eng Ethics 22, 1151–1170 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-015-9673-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-015-9673-x

Keywords

Navigation