Skip to main content
Log in

The enhanced human vs. the virtuous human: a post-phenomenological perspective

  • Student Forum
  • Published:
AI & SOCIETY Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The new generations of bioenhancement technologies and traditional Virtue Theory both try to make a meaningful connection between the improvement of human states and characteristics on one hand, and attainment to the good life, on the other. Considering the main elements of virtuousness in Farabi’s thought—namely rational inquiry and deliberative insights, alongside volitional discipline within various social contexts, one can conclude that although the trajectories of enhancement technologies—be they in the field of genetic engineering, neurostimulation technologies, or pharmacology—do not in themselves satisfy the constitutive determinants of virtuousness, they function as having both mediative and amplificative/reductive roles in a life which is dedicated to the pursuit of happiness in the light of the cultivation of virtue.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For more information about Fārābī and his philosophy, see Galston Miriam (1990) Politics and Excellence or Netton Ian (1992) Al-Fārābī and His School.

  2. Giving primacy to virtuous practice is one of the areas in which the influence of Islamic thought can be felt in Fārābī. The prominence of concepts such as ‘the greater struggle’ (al-jihād al-akbar), which is ‘the struggle against the lower self’ (jihād al-nafs), the soul which incites to evil (al-nafs al-ammāra) and the self-reproaching soul (al-nafs al-lawwāma) in the Islamic tradition have led Fārābī not to diminish the value of the practical aspects of virtuousness relative to the value of theoretical reflection.

  3. Phrases such as “The doer of the good act is better than the good [itself]; and the doer of the wicked act is worse than the wickedness [itself]” (Al-Rādī 1414:474); and “The bad deed which upsets you is better [for you] than the good deed which instills smugness and pride in you” (Āmadī 1410:402); which occur in the Islamic tradition readily lend themselves to being interpreted as falling within the virtue ethics approach.

  4. Fārābī’s sustained pleasures refer to intellectual and spiritual pleasures, but can also be interpreted to include the pleasures which are to obtain in the hereafter, given Fārābī’s religious beliefs; although the two categories are not ‌necessarily‌ distinct.

  5. One of the best illustrations of this particular experience of pleasure can be found in Tolstoy's writings. The heroes of Tolstoy's novels, such as the nobleman Nekhlyudov in his The Resurrection are usually engaged in an inner struggle between the two different accounts of pleasure.

  6. Peters characterizes the reductionist explanation of free will as an example of what Whitehead called the ‘Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness’; that is, the attempt to clarify tangible facts by means of constructs which are more abstract than the explicanda.

  7. Post-phenomenologists have challenged the monolithic views on technology using these two concepts. For instance, Verbeek challenges Borgman's ‘device paradigm’ theory using these two notions (Verbeek 2005: 189); and Aydin likewise criticizes Max Weber's Disenchantment Theory using the same method, and demonstrates that whereas science and technology disenchant the world from one perspective, that at the same time, they maintain and mediate the experience of enchantment and transcendence from some other perspective (Aydin 2015).

References

  • Al-Rādī A (1414) Nahj al-Balagha. In: Salih S (ed) Hijrat Publishing, Qom, Iran

  • Aydin C, Peter-Paul, Verbeek (2015) Transcendence in Technology. Technè Res Philosop Technol 19:3

    Google Scholar 

  • Azadpur M (2011) Reason unbound: on spiritual practice in Islamic peripatetic philosophy. State University of New York Press, Albany, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Bostrom N (2013) Why I Want to be a Posthuman When I Grow Up’. In: More M, Vita-More N (eds) The transhumanist reader. Malden, MA, Wiley-Blackwell

  • Butterworth C (1987) Medieval Islamic philosophy and the virtue of ethics. Arabica 34:221–250

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darby RR, Pascual-Leone A (2017) Moral enhancement using non-invasive brain stimulation. Front Hum Neurosci 11:77. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2017.00077

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus H (2001) On the internet. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubljevic V, Racine E (2017) Moral enhancement meets normative and empirical reality: assessing the practical feasability of moral enhancement. Bioethics 31(5):338–348

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fārābī A-N (1405) Fusul Muntaza'ah. (Eds) Najjar F Tehran, Maktabat Alzahra

  • Fārābī A-N (1413a) Tahsil al-Sa'adah. Eds. Al-Yasin J Beirut: Dar Almanahil

  • Fārābī A-N (1413b) Al-Tanbih ala Sabil al-Sa'adah. Eds Al-Yasin J. Beirut: Dar Almanahil

  • Fārābī A-N (1995) Kitab Ara’ Ahl al-Madinah al-Fadilah. Maktabat Alhilal, Beirut

    Google Scholar 

  • Fārābī A-N (1996) Kitab al-Siyasah al-Madaniyyah. Maktabat Alhilal, Beirut

    Google Scholar 

  • Galston M (1990) Politics and excellence, the political philosophy of Al-Farabi. Princeton University Press, New Jersey

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihde D (1979) Technics and praxis: a philosophy of technology. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, Don (1991) Instrumental realism: the interface between philosophy of science and philosophyof technology. The Indiana series in the philosophy of technology Bloomington: Indiana University Press

  • Ihde, Don (2015) Positioning postphenomenology Rosenberger R (eds) Postphenomenological investigations: essays on human–technology relations. Lanham, Lexington Books

  • Jones RH (2018) Limitations on the Neuroscientific Study of Mystical Experiences. Zygon: J Relig Sci 53:992–1017

  • Jotterand F (2016) Moral enhancement, neuroessentialism, and moral content. In: Jotterand F, Dubljević V (eds) Cognitive enhancement: ethical and policy implications in international perspectives. Oxford University Press, New York

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Markovits J (2010) Why be an internalist about reasons? Oxf Stud Metaethics 6:255–279

    Google Scholar 

  • Marsen S (2011) Playing by the Rules-or Not? Constructions of identity in a post human future. In: Hansell GR, Grassie W (eds) H+ Transhumanism and its Critics. Metanexus-Institute, Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • Milani M (2016) Metaphysics of love in Sufi writings. Exploring Spirituality Australia 2016:13–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters T (1997) Playing god: genetic determinism and human freedom. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Puech M (2016) The ethics of ordinary technology. Routledge, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands M (2018) What is moral enhancement? In: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 83, Cambridge University Press

  • Tennison MN (2012) Moral transhumanism: the next step. J Med Philos 37:405–416

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trothen, Tracy (2017) Moral bioenhancement from the margins: an intersectional Christian theological reconsideration. In religion and human enhancement: death, values, and morality. Eds Tracy J, Trothen and Calvin Mercer. Hampshire: Palgrave MacMillan, forthcoming

  • Vallor S (2016) Technology and the virtues: a philosophical guide to a future worth wanting. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek PP (2001) Don Ihde: the technological lifeworld. In: Achterhuis H (ed) American philosophy of technology: the empirical turn. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek PP (2005) What things do: Philosophical Reflections on Technology, Agency, and Design, Trans. Robert P. Crease, Pennsylvania State University Press, University Park, Pennsylvania

  • Verbeek PP (2009) The moral relevance of technological artefact. In: Sollie P, Düwell M (eds) Evaluating new technologies. Dordrecht, Springer, pp 63–77

  • Verbeek PP (2014) Some misunderstandings about the moral significance of technology. In: Kroes P, Verbeek PP (eds) The moral status of technical artefacts. Dordrecht, Springer

  • Wellner G (2011) Wall-window-screen: how the cell phone mediates a worldview for us. Humanit Technol Rev 30:77–104

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker M (2018) Genetic engineering, virtue-first enhancement, and deification in Neo-Irenaean Theodicy. Theol Sci 16:251–272. https://doi.org/10.1080/14746700.2018.1488472

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mostafa Taqavi.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Taebnia, V., Taqavi, M. The enhanced human vs. the virtuous human: a post-phenomenological perspective. AI & Soc 36, 1057–1068 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-020-01082-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-020-01082-z

Keywords

Navigation