Skip to main content
Log in

On the outcome equivalence of backward induction and extensive form rationalizability

  • Published:
International Journal of Game Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Pearce’s (Econometrica 52:1029–1050, 1984) extensive-form rationalizablity (EFR) is a solution concept embodying a best-rationalization principle (Battigalli, Games Econ Behav 13:178–200, 1996; Battigalli and Siniscalchi, J Econ Theory 106:356–391, 2002) for forward-induction reasoning. EFR strategies may hence be distinct from backward-induction (BI) strategies. We provide a direct and transparent proof that, in perfect-information games with no relevant ties, the unique BI outcome is nevertheless identical to the unique EFR outcome, even when the EFR strategy profile and the BI strategy profile are distinct.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. That is, games where each player’s payoffs are distinct from one another in the leaves which follow each of this player’s decision nodes.

  2. Somewhat of a misnomer—if the player at the root of the game has a dominated move and she chooses it, at subsequent nodes the other players ‘strongly believe she is rational’ by attributing to her up-front irrationality.

  3. Like EFR, also explicable equilibrium is based on some kind of best-rationalization principle. However, the two concepts are different.

  4. To be more precise, the condition in Pearce and Battigalli is equivalent to Bayesian updating, in the sense that it gives the same probability ratios for strategies that are not ruled out by information sets, but it does not require “normalization”.

  5. It can be shown, namely, that whenever a strategy is optimal for a belief vector that strongly believes a set of opponents’ strategy profiles, then it is also optimal for an equivalent belief vector that strongly believes this same set of strategy profiles, and which satisfies Bayesian updating.

  6. Here, a plan of action represents a class of behaviorally equivalent strategies, that is, a class of strategies that reach the same decision nodes for player \(i\), and make the same choices at these decision nodes. Actually, it can be shown that not only the plans of action induced by \(S_{i}^{\infty }\) are the same in our setting as in Pearce’s and Battigalli’s, but also the plans of action induced by \(S_{i}^{k}\), at every step \(k\) of the procedure.

References

  • Arieli I, Aumann RJ (2012) The logic of backward induction, Working paper

  • Battigalli P (1996) Strategic rationality orderings and the best rationalization principle. Games Econ Behav 13:178–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Battigalli P (1997) On rationalizability in extensive games. J Econ Theory 74:40–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Battigalli P, Siniscalchi M (2002) Strong belief and forward induction reasoning. J Econ Theory 106:356–391

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen J, Micali S (2013) The order independence of iterated dominance in extensive games. Theor Econ 8:125–163

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen J, Micali S (2011) The robustness of extensive-form rationalizability, Working paper

  • Church A, Rosser JB (1936) Some properties of conversion. Trans Am Math Soc 39:472–482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gretlein RJ (1983) Dominance elimination procedures on finite alternative games. Int J Game Theory 12:107–113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg E, Mertens J-F (1986) On the strategic stability of equilibria. Econometrica 54:1003–1037

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marx L, Swinkels J (1997) Order independence for iterated weak dominance. Games Econ Behav 18:219–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marx L, Swinkels J (2000) Order independence for iterated weak dominance. Games Econ Behav 31:324–329

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearce D (1984) Rationalizable strategic behavior and the problem of perfection. Econometrica 52:1029–1050

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perea A (2014) Belief in the opponents’ future rationality. Games Econ Behav 83:231–254

    Google Scholar 

  • Perea A (2012) Epistemic game theory: reasoning and choice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reny PJ (1992) Backward induction, normal form perfection and explicable equilibria. Econometrica 60:627–649

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein A (1991) Comments on the interpretation of game theory. Econometrica 59:909–924

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shimoji M, Watson J (1998) Conditional dominance, rationalizability, and game forms. J Econ Theory 83:161–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank an associate editor and two referees for very useful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aviad Heifetz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Heifetz, A., Perea, A. On the outcome equivalence of backward induction and extensive form rationalizability. Int J Game Theory 44, 37–59 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-014-0418-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-014-0418-x

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation