Skip to main content
Log in

Voluntary ambiguity in incentive contracts

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
OR Spectrum Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Because accounting standards allow for some discretion in their application, accounting numbers often result from the choice of one possible interpretation among several. This paper investigates the optimal choice of a principal when this information is used for stewardship: whether committing ex-ante to using one specific interpretation, the more informative one, or keeping the ambiguity and opportunistically choosing ex-post the performance measure the least favorable to the agent. The choice between ambiguity and commitment involves a trade-off between the potential windfall for the agent (higher with commitment) and the risk of undeserved punishment (higher with ambiguity). The optimal policy depends on the risk aversion of the agent and of the extent of the ambiguity: high risk aversion and a large number of interpretations being in favor of ex-ante commitment.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In a related vein, Dye (2002) note that accounting reports involve a lot of dichotomous choices (going concern or not, capital lease or operating leases) which suppress many probabilistic nuances.

  2. Usually, the term “informativeness” is applied for a whole distribution and not with regard to only one outcome. Ewert and Wagenhofer (2012), for instance, use the term “informational content” instead. By contrast, and for an easy reading of the paper, I have decided to use the term “informativeness” even when referring to the informational content of only one outcome.

  3. When one task is contractible whereas another one is not (thus, a subjectivity assessment of this second task is compulsory), it may be optimal to keep ambiguity on the reward of the contractible task in order to have more threats available (see Bernheim and Whinston 1998). Again, this explanation, based on congruity and gaming issues, is complementary to ours, which is based on risk sharing in incomplete incentive contracts.

  4. I conjecture that the results (especially Proposition 2) hold for a more general utility function, provided that the relative risk aversion coefficient keeps enough regularity.

  5. For instance, when ambiguity regards the possibility to control, or not, for external factors (that is, factors beyond the control of the agent), then keeping this ambiguity is never optimal. The principal has the choice between two signals, one of which (the performance measure without controlling for external factor) is a garbling of the other one (the same measure that controls for external factors).

  6. If the same information system were more informative in both states of the world, then the mean preserving spread criterion of Kim (1995) would apply. The principal would always prefer this information system.

  7. A natural question is whether the converse also holds. While I was not able to show it, numerical simulations lead me to conjecture that there is indeed a cutoff level of risk aversion such that ex-ante commitment is optimal if and only if the risk aversion of the agent is above this level.

  8. Several studies have documented that this probability is, for managers, often higher than two thirds, see for instance Merchant and Manzoni (1989) and Murphy (2001).

References

  • Arya A, Glover J (2008) Performance measurement manipulation: cherry-picking what to correct. Rev Account Stud 13:119–139

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker G, Gibbons R, Murphy K (1994) Subjective performances in optimal incentive contracts. Q J Econ 109:1125–1156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim BD, Whinston MD (1998) Incomplete contracts and strategic ambiguity. Am Econ Rev 88:902–932

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen J, Demski J (2004) Asymmetric monitoring: good versus bad news verification. Schmalenbach Bus Rev 56:206–222

    Google Scholar 

  • Dye R (1985) Costly contract contingencies. Int Econ Rev 26:233–250

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dye R (2002) Classification manipulation and nash accounting standards. J Account Res 40:1125–1162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ederer F, Holden R, Meyer M (2010) Gaming and strategic ambiguity in incentive provision. http://mylaw2.usc.edu/centers/cleo/workshops/documents/Ederer.pdf

  • Ewert R, Wagenhofer A (2012) Earnings management, conservatism, and earnings quality. Found Trends Account 6(2):65–186

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmstrom B (1979) Moral hazard and observability. Bell J Econ 10:74–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim SK (1995) Efficiency of an informartion system in an agency model. Econometrica 63(1):89–102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kwon Y, Newman D, Suh Y (2001) The demand for accounting conservatism for management control. Rev Account Stud 6:29–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larmande F, Ponssard J (2013) Fishing for excuses and performance evaluation. Working Paper. http://ssrn.com/abstract=2268004

  • Levin J (2003) Relational incentive contracts. Am Econ Rev 93:835–847

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacLeod B (2003) Optimal contracting with subjective evaluation. Am Econ Rev 93(1):216–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melumad N, Mookherjee D, Reichelstein S (1997) Contract complexity, incentives and the value of delegation. J Econ Manage Strategy 6:257–289

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merchant K, Manzoni JF (1989) The achievability of budget targets in profit centers: a field study. Account Rev 64:539–558

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy K (2001) Performance standards in incentive contracts. J Account Econ 30(3):245–278

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ozbilgin M, Penno M (2008) The assignment of decision rights in formal information systems. J Manage Account Res 20:83–105

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rajan MV, Reichelstein S (2009) Objective versus subjective indicators of managerial performance. Account Rev 84:209–237

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank the guest Editor, two anonymous referees, John Christensen, Marco Trombetta (discussant) and participants at the 2012 Annual Congress of the European Accounting Association and at the 2012 Workshop on Accounting and Economics in Segovia for their useful comments and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to F. Larmande.

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 Proof of Lemma 1

First, the proof of (6). Note that:

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{s_1(e)}{s_1(0)} < \frac{m(e)}{m(0)} \\&\quad \quad \Leftrightarrow (p(e)\pi _1+(1-p(e))(1-\pi _1)) \left( p(0)\prod _{i=1}^{N}\pi _i +(1-p(0))\prod _{i=1}^{N}(1-\pi _i) \right) \\&\quad < (p(0)\pi _1+(1-p(0))(1-\pi _1)) \left( p(e) \prod _{i=1}^{N}\pi _i +(1-p(e))\prod _{i=1}^{N}(1-\pi _i) \right) \\&\quad \Leftrightarrow p(e)\pi _1(1-\pi _1) \prod _{i=2}^{N}(1-\pi _i) + p(0)\pi _1(1-\pi _1) \prod _{i=2}^{N}\pi _i \\&\quad < p(0)\pi _1(1-\pi _1) \prod _{i=2}^{N}(1-\pi _i) + p(e)\pi _1(1-\pi _1) \prod _{i=2}^{N}\pi _i \end{aligned}$$

Thus, as \(1-\pi _1>0\),

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{s_1(e)}{s_1(0)} < \frac{m(e)}{m(0)} \Leftrightarrow \prod _{i=2}^{N}(1-\pi _i) <\prod _{i=2}^{N}\pi _i \end{aligned}$$

which is clearly the case because \(\pi _2>1/2\) and the others \(\pi \ge 1/2\). Thus (6) holds.

Now, the proof of the inequality (7):

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{1-s_1(e)}{1-s_1(0)} < \frac{1-m(e)}{1-m(0)}\\&\quad \Leftrightarrow ((1-p(e))\pi _1+p(e)(1-\pi _1)) \left( 1-p(0)\prod _{i=1}^{N}\pi _i -(1-p(0))\prod _{i=1}^{N}(1-\pi _i)\right) \\&\quad < ((1-p(0))\pi _1+p(0)(1-\pi _1)) \left( 1-p(e) \prod _{i=1}^{N}\pi _i-(1-p(e))\prod _{i=1}^{N}(1-\pi _i)\right) \\&\quad \Leftrightarrow p(e)(1-2\pi _1)-p(0)\pi _1^2 \prod _{i=2}^{N}\pi _i-p(e)(1-\pi _1)^2\prod _{i=2}^{N}(1-\pi _i)\\&\quad < p(0)(1-2\pi _1)-p(e)\pi _1^2 \prod _{i=2}^{N}\pi _i -p(0)(1-\pi _1)^2\prod _{i=2}^{N}(1-\pi _i)\\&\quad \Leftrightarrow \pi _1^2 \prod _{i=2}^{N}\pi _i < (1-\pi _1)^2\prod _{i=2}^{N}(1-\pi _i) + (2\pi _1-1) \end{aligned}$$

As \(\pi _1 < 1\), the inequality (7) is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} \pi _1^2 \left( \prod _{i=2}^{N}\pi _i -1\right)&< (1-\pi _1)^2\left( \prod _{i=2}^{N}(1-\pi _i) -1\right) \nonumber \\&\Leftrightarrow \frac{1 -\prod _{i=2}^{N}(1-\pi _i ) }{1-\prod _{i=2}^{N}\pi _i } < \frac{\pi _1^2}{(1-\pi _1)^2} \end{aligned}$$
(10)

Thus, if (10) holds, inequality (7) will follow. I am going to show it by iteration (more precisely, that for all \(1\ge \pi _1 \ge \pi _2 \ge \cdots \ge \pi _N \ge 1/2\) with \(\pi _1>1/2\), (10) holds).

First, for the rank \(N=2\), this is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\pi _2}{1-\pi _2} < \frac{\pi _1^2}{(1-\pi _1)^2} \end{aligned}$$

As \(1 \ge \pi _1\ge \pi _2 \ge 0,\,\frac{\pi _2}{(1-\pi _2)} \le \frac{\pi _1}{(1-\pi _1)}\). And as \(\pi _1>1/2\), \(\frac{\pi _1}{(1-\pi _1)}<\frac{\pi _1^2}{(1-\pi _1)^2}\). The result holds for the rank \(N=2\).

Assume the assumption true at the rank \(N-1\). If \(\pi _2=1/2\) then \(\pi _N = \cdots =\pi _2=1/2\). Moreover \(\pi _1>1/2\). Thus

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1 -\prod _{i=2}^{N}(1-\pi _i ) }{1-\prod _{i=2}^{N}\pi _i } =\frac{1 -\prod _{i=2}^{N}1/2 }{1-\prod _{i=2}^{N} 1/2 } = 1 < \frac{\pi _1^2}{(1-\pi _1)^2} \end{aligned}$$

and (10) holds at the rank \(N\). If \(\pi _2>1/2\), it is possible to apply (10) at the rank \(N-1\) to the collection \(\pi _2 \ge \cdots \ge \pi _N \):

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1 -\prod _{i=3}^{N}(1-\pi _i ) }{1-\prod _{i=3}^{N}\pi _i } < \frac{\pi _2^2}{(1-\pi _2)^2} \end{aligned}$$
(11)

Moreover,

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{1 -\prod _{i=2}^{N}(1-\pi _i ) }{1-\prod _{i=2}^{N}\pi _i }< \frac{\pi _2}{1-\pi _2} \nonumber \\&\quad \Leftrightarrow \frac{1 -\prod _{i=2}^{N}(1-\pi _i ) }{\pi _2}< \frac{1-\prod _{i=2}^{N}\pi _i }{1-\pi _2}\nonumber \\&\quad \Leftrightarrow \frac{1 -(1-\pi _2)+(1-\pi _2)-\prod _{i=2}^{N}(1-\pi _i) }{\pi _2}< \frac{1-\pi _2+\pi _2-\prod _{i=2}^{N}\pi _i }{1-\pi _2}\nonumber \\&\quad \Leftrightarrow \frac{1-\pi _2}{\pi _2} \left( 1 -\prod _{i=3}^{N}(1-\pi _i )\right) < \frac{\pi _2}{1-\pi _2} \left( 1-\prod _{i=3}^{N}\pi _i \right) \end{aligned}$$
(12)

which holds, given (11). Thus (12) holds. As \(\frac{\pi _2}{(1-\pi _2)} \le \frac{\pi _1}{(1-\pi _1)} < \frac{\pi _1^2}{(1-\pi _1)^2} \), (10) holds at the rank \(N\).

1.2 Proof of Lemma 2

\( \frac{q(e)}{q(0)} < \frac{h(e)}{h(0)} \Leftrightarrow \frac{h(e)-h(0)}{h(0)}> \frac{q(e)-q(0)}{q(0)} \Leftrightarrow -\frac{h(0)}{h(e)-h(0)} > -\frac{q(0)}{q(e)-q(0)} \Leftrightarrow u^-_{q} < u^-_h\)

\(\frac{1-q(e)}{1-q(0)} < \frac{1-h(e)}{1-h(0)} \Leftrightarrow \frac{q(e)-q(0)}{1-q(0)} > \frac{h(e)-h(0)}{1-h(0)} \Leftrightarrow \frac{1-q(0)}{q(e)-q(0)} < \frac{1-h(0)}{h(e)-h(0)} \Leftrightarrow u^+_{q} < u^+_h \)

1.3 Proof of Proposition 1

I am going to provide two sets of parameters, one for which ex-ante commitment is optimal and the other for which ambiguity is optimal.

Example 1—ex-ante commitment is optimal. Assume \(p(e)=0.75,\,p(0)=0.25,\,C=8,\,N=2,\,\pi _1=0.8,\,\pi _2=0.6\), \(u_\mathrm{res}=10\) and \(\alpha =0.5\). Then \(\mathrm{IC}_1=121\) and \(\mathrm{IC}_m=175\): ex-ante commitment is optimal.

Example 2—ambiguity is optimal. Assume \(p(e)=0.75\), \(p(0)=0.6,\,C=10,\,N=2,\,\pi _1=0.6,\,\pi _2=0.59,\,u_\mathrm{res}=300\) and \(\alpha =0.99\). Then \(\mathrm{IC}_1=325.70\) and \(\mathrm{IC}_m=325.59\): ambiguity is optimal.

1.4 Proof of Proposition 2

First the proof that, when risk aversion is large enough, ex-ante commitment is optimal. Ex-ante commitment is optimal if and only if \(\mathrm{IC}_m>\mathrm{IC}_1\) that is

$$\begin{aligned} m(e)(u^+_m)^{1/\alpha } + (1-m(e)) (u^-_m)^{1/\alpha } - s_1(e)(u^+_1)^{1/\alpha } - (1-s_1(e)) (u^-_1)^{1/\alpha }>0\nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(13)

where the four \(u^i_j\) do not depend on \(\alpha \). Let \(D(\alpha )\) denote the LHS of the above inequality. Lemmas 1 and 2 entail that \(u^+_m\) is strictly higher than the other three \(u^i_j\). Thus \(D(\alpha )/(u^+_m)^{1/\alpha }\) goes to \(m(e)\) when \(\alpha \) goes to zero. As \(m(e)>0\) there is an \(\alpha _{\lim }\) such that \(\forall \alpha \le \alpha _{\lim },\, D(\alpha )/(u^+_m)^{1/\alpha }>0\). Thus \(\forall \alpha \le \alpha _{\lim }\), that is if as soon as the agent is sufficiently risk averse, ex-ante commitment is optimal.

Now the proof of the second part of the proposition: if \(N\) is large enough, then, again, ex-ante commitment is optimal.

The only property of the power utility function, \(u(y)=y^\alpha /\alpha \) that is needed is \(u'(y) \rightarrow _{y \rightarrow \infty } 0\). Denote \(x_\mathrm{max}= \lim _{y \rightarrow \infty }u(y)\). With the power utility function \(x_\mathrm{max}\) is infinite but it might be finite with other utility functions.

As \(f'(x)=1/u'(f(x)),\,u'(y) \rightarrow _{y \rightarrow \infty } 0 \Leftrightarrow f'(x) \rightarrow _{x \rightarrow x_\mathrm{max}} + \infty \). I am going to show, first, that

$$\begin{aligned} f(x)/x \rightarrow _{x \rightarrow x_\mathrm{max}} + \infty \end{aligned}$$
(14)

Let \(M>0\). As \(f'(x) \rightarrow _{x \rightarrow x_\mathrm{max}} + \infty \), \(\exists x_M>0\) such that \(f'(x) \ge 2M\) for all \(x\) above \(x_M\). Thus \(\forall x \ge x_M,\,f(x)-f(x_M) \ge 2M(x-x_M)\). Moreover, \(f(x_M) \ge 0\). Thus \(\forall x \ge 2x_M,\,f(x)/x \ge 2M(x-x_M)/x \ge M\).

Let \(\mathrm{IC}_N\) denote the incentive cost with ambiguity and N signals. Denote \(m_N(a)\), the probability of obtaining a good result in the ambiguity case when there are \(N\) signals:

$$\begin{aligned} m_N(a)&=p(a)\prod _{i=1}^{N}\pi _i+(1-p(a))\prod _{i=1}^{N}(1-\pi _i) \end{aligned}$$

As \(\forall i,\,(1-\pi _i) \le 1/2\) and \( \pi _i \le \pi _1,\,m_N(a) \le p(a) (\pi _1)^N+(1-p(a)) (1/2)^N\). Thus, \(m_N(a)\) goes to zero when \(N\) goes to \(+\infty \).

Lemma 1 ensures that \(\frac{s_1(e)}{s_1(0)} < \frac{m(e)}{m(0)}\) and, thus, from Lemma 2, \(u_N^- \ge u_1^-\).

$$\begin{aligned} \mathrm{IC}_N&= m_N(e) f \left( u^+_N \right) +(1-m_N(e))f(u^-_N) \\&\ge m_N(e) f \left( \frac{1-m_N(0)}{m_N(e)-m_N(0)}C + u_\mathrm{res} \right) +(1-m_N(e))f(u^-_1)\\&\ge m_N(e) f \left( \frac{(1-m_N(0))C+ u_\mathrm{res}m_N(e)}{m_N(e)} \right) +\min (0,f(u^-_1)) \end{aligned}$$

As \(\forall a\,m_N(a)\) goes to zero when \(N\) goes to infinity, \(((1-m_N(0))C+ u_\mathrm{res}m_N(e))\) goes to \(C\) and thus is above \(C/2\) for \(N\) high enough. Then

$$\begin{aligned} \mathrm{IC}_N&\ge \frac{C}{2} \frac{2m_N(e)}{C} f \left( \frac{C}{2m_N(e)} \right) +\min (0,f(u^-_1)) \end{aligned}$$

Since \(\frac{C}{2m_N(e)}\) goes to \(+\infty \), (14) implies that \(\mathrm{IC}_N\) goes to \(+\infty \). As a result, \(\mathrm{IC}_N\) is always higher than \(\mathrm{IC}_1\) for \(N\) high enough.

1.5 Proof of Lemma 3

When \(p(e)>1/2\), the lower \(\pi \), the higher the probability of obtaining a poor result. This is the case because the probability of obtaining a poor result is \(1-s(a)=p(a) - (2p(a)-1) \pi \). On the other hand, the lower \(\pi \), the lower the informativeness, as both likelihood ratios (poor and good outcomes) worsen.

1.6 Proof of Lemma 4

Assume that the probability of obtaining a good future value is no more \(p(a)\) but \(q(a)=(1-p(a))\). Denote probability q this assumption, while the initial assumption will be denoted probability p. Denote \(s_1^q(a)\), the probability that the first signal is good under probability q, while \(s_1^p(a)\) is the same probability under probability p.

$$\begin{aligned} s_1^q(a)&=q(a)\pi _1+(1-q(a))(1-\pi _1) \\&= (1-p(a))\pi _1 + p(a)(1-\pi _1) \\&= 1 - (p(a)\pi _1+(1-p(a))(1-\pi _1) \\&= 1-s_1^p(a) \end{aligned}$$

Thus

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1-s_1^p(e)}{1-s_1^p(0)} = \frac{s_1^q(e)}{s_1^q(0)} \end{aligned}$$
(15)

and

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{s_1^p(e)}{s_1^p(0)}=\frac{1-s_1^q(e)}{1-s_1^q(0)} \end{aligned}$$
(16)

Denote now \(m^q(a)\) the probability that the ambiguity monitoring technology leads to a good evaluation under probability q.

$$\begin{aligned} m^q(a)&=q(a) \prod _1^N \pi _i+ (1-q(a)) \prod _1^N (1-\pi _i) \\&= (1-p(a)) \prod _1^N \pi _i+ p(a) \prod _1^N (1-\pi _i) \\ \end{aligned}$$

Denote \(M^p(a)\) the probability of obtaining a good evaluation when the agent chooses the performance measure under probability p.

$$\begin{aligned} M^p(a)&= 1 - \left( p(a) \prod _1^N (1-\pi _i) + (1-p(a)) \prod _1^N \pi _i \right) \\&= 1- m^q(a) \end{aligned}$$

Thus

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1-M^p(e)}{1-M^p(0)} = \frac{M^q(e)}{M^q(0)} \end{aligned}$$
(17)

and

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{M^p(e)}{M^p(0)}=\frac{1-M^q(e)}{1-M^q(0)} \end{aligned}$$
(18)

Given (15), (16), (17) and (18), Lemma 4 is a corollary of Lemma 1 applied to probability q.

1.7 Proof of Proposition 3

I am first going to use the same examples as in the proof of Proposition 1. Then I will provide an example where agent’s choice is optimal. Let \(\mathrm{IC}_M\) denote the incentive cost with the agent’s choice monitoring technology.

Example 1—ex-ante commitment is optimal. Assume \(p(e)=0.75,\,p(0)=0.25,\,C=8,\,N=2,\,\pi _1=0.8,\,\pi _2=0.6\), \(u_\mathrm{res}=10\) and \(\alpha =0.5\). Then \(\mathrm{IC}_1=121,\,\mathrm{IC}_m=175\) and \(\mathrm{IC}_M= 140\): ex-ante commitment is optimal.

Example 2—ambiguity is optimal. Assume \(p(e)=0.75\), \(p(0)=0.6,\,C=10,\,N=2,\,\pi _1=0.6,\,\pi _2=0.59,\,u_\mathrm{res}=300\) and \(\alpha =0.99\). Then \(\mathrm{IC}_1=325.70,\,\mathrm{IC}_m=325.59\) and \(\mathrm{IC}_M=325.70\): ambiguity is optimal.

Example 3—agent’s choice is optimal. Assume \(p(e)=0.75\), \(p(0)=0.25,\,C=2,\,N=2,\,\pi _1=0.8,\,\pi _2=0.6,\,u_\mathrm{res}=10\) and \(\alpha =0.1\). Then \(\mathrm{IC}_1=24,\,\mathrm{IC}_m=151\) and \(\mathrm{IC}_M= 21\): agent’s choice is optimal.

1.8 Proof of Proposition 4

In the proof of the first part of Proposition 2, the only property of the two monitoring technologies that has been used is that \(u^+_m >u^+_1\), which given Lemma 2 comes from Eq. (7). Given (9), \(u^+_m >u^+_M\) and \(u^+_1 >u^+_M\). Thus the same proof gives that when the risk aversion of the agent is above a certain threshold, agent’s choice is optimal compared to the two other monitoring technologies.

Now, the proof of the second part of the proposition. Let \(M_N(a)\) denotes the probability \(M(a)\) when \(N\) signals are available. As \(\forall i\,1/2 \le \pi _i \le \pi _1\),

$$\begin{aligned} 1-M_N(a) \le p(a) (1/2)^N + (1-p(a)) (\pi _1)^N \end{aligned}$$

As \(\pi _1<1\), when \(N\) goes to \(+\infty \), the RHS of the above inequality goes to zero for all \(a\). Thus both \(M_N(e)\) and \(M_N(0)\) goes to 1 when \(N\) goes to \(+\infty \). As a result, \(u_\mathrm{res} - M_N(0)C/(M_N(e)-M_N(0))\) goes to \(-\infty \) when \(N\) goes to \(+\infty \). Thus for \(N\) large enough: \(u_\mathrm{res} < M_N(0)C/(M_N(e)-M_N(0))\). Then the optimal wages of the agent’s choice monitoring technology are no longer provided by (3) and (4). \(w^-\) cannot be lower than 0 while keeping an expected utility higher than \(-\infty \). The optimal rewards are then \(w^+_{M_N} = f( C/ (M_N(e)-M_N(0))\) and \(w^-_{M_N}=0\). As \(M_N(e)\) go to 1 and \(w^+_{M_N}\) goes to \(+\infty \), the incentive cost goes to \(+\infty \) when \(N\) goes to \(+\infty \), whereas the incentive cost with ex-ante commitment remains fixed. Thus, for \(N\) large enough, ex-ante commitment is optimal compared to agent’s choice. Given Proposition 2, when \(N\) is large enough, ex-ante commitment is also optimal compared to ambiguity.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Larmande, F. Voluntary ambiguity in incentive contracts. OR Spectrum 35, 957–974 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00291-013-0351-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00291-013-0351-6

Keywords

Navigation