Skip to main content
Log in

The symbol detachment problem

  • Research Report
  • Published:
Cognitive Processing Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In situated and embodied approaches it is commonly assumed that the dynamics of sensorimotor engagement between an adaptive agent and its environment are crucial in understanding natural cognition. This perspective permits to address the symbol grounding problem, since the aboutness of any mental state arising during agent-environment engagement is guaranteed by their continuous coupling. However, cognitive agents are also able to formulate representations that are detached from the current state of affairs, such as expectations and goals. Moreover, they can act on their representations before—or instead of—acting directly on the environment, for example building the plan of a bridge and not directly the bridge. On the basis of representations, actions such as planning, remembering or imagining are possible that are disengaged from the current sensorimotor cycle, and often functional to future-oriented conducts. A new problem thus has to be acknowledged, the symbol detachment problem: how and why do situated agents develop representations that are detached from their current sensorimotor interaction, but nevertheless preserve grounding and aboutness? How do cognitive agents progressively acquire a range of capabilities permitting them to deal not only with the current situation but also with alternative, in particular future states of affairs? How do they develop the capability of acting on their representations instead of acting directly on the world? In a theoretical and developmental perspective, we propose that anticipation plays a crucial role in the detachment process: anticipatory representations, originally detached from the sensorimotor cycle for the sake of action control, are successively exapted for bootstrapping increasingly complex cognitive capabilities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Notes

  1. A caveat: with the term “detachment” we are not embracing here the idea that cognition is detached from the nature and functioning of organisms or their environments. We claim instead that some organisms have internal models of their environments serving the function of representing it, although not being causally determined by current stimuli (here comes the term “detachment”); that the organisms can act on their representations before or instead of acting directly on their environments (here comes the term “disengagement”); and that nevertheless the final goal of this form of cognition is acting in the environment. Our point here thus in not to defend the idea that acting on representations is the unique, or a privileged form of cognition, but to investigate how and why it is possible in natural and artificial organisms.

  2. However, it is not—just for this—a “representation” of itself, unless it satisfies the usual criteria for representation. That is, the environment can be used as a representation of itself only under specific circumstances. Not only it is not “the best representation of itself”, as claimed by Brooks (1991), since it is noisy, complex, and full of information hard to be accessed; but in many cases it is not a representation at all. Never we should mix up ‘id quod intelligitur’ (that which we know, the object the representation is about) with ‘id quo intelligitur’ (that by which we know, the vehicle) (Aquinas 1947).

  3. Our emphasis on simulative theories is not intended to deny the role of other dynamics such as social ones: we learn many concepts and practices via social interaction and coordinated actions over a shared physical world (Vygotsky 1978). However, simulation can be crucially involved in those dynamics, too, as indicated by the empirical literature already reviewed.

  4. Due to its multiple functions, the term goal has been ambiguosly used for explaining different phenomena, that can also imply different coding: (1) guiding and regulating actual action, and (2) conceiving possible outcomes outside any actual immediate action. This point is clearly illustrated by Gallese and Metzinger (2003), who firstly discuss about the role of goals in the action: “In the monkey brain microcosm so far explored, the goal of grasping an object is still almost completely overlapping with the action-control strategies. Action control actually equates to the definition of the action goal: the goal is represented as a goal-state, namely, as a successfully terminated action pattern” and thereafter introduce a notion of goals which is not engaged in here-and-now action: “However, the presence in the monkey brain of neurons coding the goal of grasping, regardless of which effector (hand or mouth) will eventually achieve it, in our opinion provides evolutionary evidence of the dawning of a more complex—and abstract— coding of intention and volition.” We will discuss in Sect. 5 that these phenomena occur at different stages of the detachment process.

  5. This fact makes harder empirical investigations of these phenomena. Another source of difficulty is the fact that some cognitive functionalities do not simply emerge at a certain stage, but change over time, and this somewhat erroneously suggest that the same mechanism could be in play. This is for example the case of the development of objects permanence in children, that becomes increasingly complex at different stages of detachment and is performed using different forms of anticipation, first implicit and later on explicit. As reported by Piaget (1954), initially children have no object permanence. Successively, when they develop implicit anticipatory capabilities, object permanence is realized procedurally, by a continuous coupling between the mechanism and the object to track. At a later stage, only after having acquired a detached representation of the object to track, it is possible acquire episodic and not only categorical knowledge, i.e. to express: ‘take that ball’ and not only ‘take a ball’. The object is now affordable for abstract thinking: it is possible to refer to a never perceived or to a non existent ball, to formulate beliefs about the ball, and to take other’s perspective about the ball.

  6. We are not supposing here, however, that all goals have an hedonistic nature, since the valence they carry on can acquire a sufficient degree of autonomy from immediate drives (e.g. the value of money), and they can have different origins. Many goals and goal-oriented conducts have a social origin and do not depend immediately from drives; suitable mechanisms can be for example imitation and internalization of cultural practices (Vygotsky 1978).

  7. Several theories have been recently proposed that situate representations and conceptual knowledge in different brain areas. The most extreme ‘embodied cognition’ position is taken by Gallese and Lakoff (2005), who argue that integrative processes take place into the sensorimotor system, thus denying any role for higher association areas. This position is disputed by Mahon and Caramazza (2005) on the basis of neurobiological findings that are difficult to explain on the basis of a purely motor theory of action.

References

  • Adams JA (1971) A closed-loop theory of motor learning. J Mot Behav 3:111–149

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas ST (1947) The Summa Theologica. Benziger Bros

  • Balkenius C, Hulth N (1999) Attention as selection-for-action: a scheme for active perception. In: Proceedings of EuRobot-1999, Zurich

  • Barsalou LW (1983) Ad hoc categories. Mem Cognit 11(3):211–227

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou LW (1999) Perceptual symbol systems. Behav Brain Sci 22:577–600

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou LW (2003) Abstraction in perceptual symbol systems. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 358(1435):1177–1187

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (2001) Function, anticipation and representation. In: Dubois DM (ed) Computing anticipatory systems. CASYS 2000-Fourth international conference. American Institute of Physics, Melville, pp 459–469

  • Blakemore S-J, Decety J (2001) From the perception of action to the understanding of intention. Nat Rev Neurosci 2:561–7

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano F (1985) Psychology from an empirical standpoint. Translated by Rancurello AC, Terrell DB, McAlister LL Routledge, London

  • Brooks RA (1991) Intelligence without representation. Artif Intell 47(47):139–159

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butz MV, Hoffmann J (2002) Anticipations control behavior: animal behavior in an anticipatory learning classifier system. Adapt Behav 10(2):75–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castelfranchi C (1995) Guarantees for autonomy in cognitive agent architecture. In: Wooldridge M, Jennings NR (eds) Intelligent agents: theories, architectures, and languages. number 890 in LNAI, Springer, pp 56–70

  • Castelfranchi C (2005) Mind as an anticipatory device: for a theory of expectations. In: BVAI 2005, pp 258–276

  • Castelfranchi C, Paglieri F (2007) The role of beliefs in goal dynamics: prolegomena to a constructive theory of intentions. Synthese, to appear

  • Clark A (1997) Being there. Putting brain, body, and world together. MIT Press, Cambridge, USA

  • Clark A, Chalmers DJ (1998) The extended mind. Analysis 58:10–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A, Grush R (1999) Towards a cognitive robotics. Adapt Behav 7(1):5–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombo M, Graziano M (1994) Effects of auditory and visual interference on auditory-visual delayed matching to sample in monkeys (maca fascicularis). Behav Neurosci 108:636–639

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio AR (1989) Time-locked multiregional retroactivation: a systems-level proposal for the neural substrates of recall and recognition. Cognition 33:25–62

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio AR (1994) Descartes’ error: emotion, reason and the human brain. Grosset/Putnam, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Decety J (1996) Do imagined and executed actions share the same neural substrate? Brain Res Cogn 3:87–93

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Decety J, Chaminade T (2003) When the self represents the other: a new cognitive neuroscience view on psychological identification. Conscious Cogn 12(20):577–596

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1991) Consciousness explained. Little Brown & Co. Boston, USA

    Google Scholar 

  • Desmurget M, Grafton S (2000) Forward modeling allows feedback control for fast reaching movements. Trends Cogn Sci 4:423–431

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Doya K (2002) Metalearning and neuromodulation. Neural Netw 15(4–6):495–506

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Drescher GL (1991) Made-up minds: a constructivist approach to artificial intelligence. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fogassi L, Ferrari P, Chersi F, Gesierich B, Rozzi S, Rizzolatti G (2005) Parietal lobe: from action organization to intention understanding. Science 308:662–667

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Frith CD, Blakemore S, Wolpert DM (2000) Explaining the symptoms of schizophrenia: abnormalities in the awareness of action. Brain Res Brain Res Rev 31(2–3):357–363

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V (2000) The inner sense of action: agency and motor representations. J Conscious Stud 7:23–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V (2001) The ’shared manifold’ hypothesis. from mirror neurons to empathy. J Conscious Stud 8:5–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V, Goldman A (1998) Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading. Trends Cogn Sci 2(12):493–501

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V, Lakoff G (2005) The brain’s concepts: The role of the sensory-motor system in reason and language. Cogn Neuropsychol 22:455–479

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V, Metzinger T (2003) Motor ontology: the representational reality of goals, actions, and selves. Philos Psychol 13(3):365–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardenfors P (2004) Cooperation and the evolution of symbolic communication. In: Oller K, Griebel U (eds) Evolution of communication systems: a comparative approach. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 237–256

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardenfors P, Orvath M (2005) The evolution of anticipatory cognition as a precursor to symbolic communication. In: Brook S (eds) In: Proceedings of the Morris symposium on the evolution of language. NY, USA

  • Gibson J (1966) The senses considered as perceptual systems. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg A (1997) What memory is for. Behav Brain Sci 20:1–55

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Grush R (2004) The emulation theory of representation: motor control, imagery, and perception. Behav Brain Sci 27(3):377–396

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Harnad S (1990) The symbol grounding problem. Physica D 42:335–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hesslow G (2002) Conscious thought as simulation of behaviour and perception. Trends Cogn Sci 6:242–247

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann J (2003) Anticipatory behavioral control. In: Butz M, et al. (eds) Anticipatory behavior in adaptive learning systems: foundations, theories, and systems. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 44–65

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann H (2007) Perception through visuomotor anticipation in a mobile robot. Neural Netw 20:22–33

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • von Holst E, Mittelstaedt H (1950) Das reafferenzprinzip. Naturwissenschaften 37:464–476

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hommel B, Musseler J, Aschersleben G, Prinz W (2001) The theory of event coding (tec): a framework for perception and action planning. Behav Brain Sci 24(5):849–78

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley SL (2005) Active perception and perceiving action: the shared circuits hypothesis. In: Gendler T, Hawthorne J (eds) Perceptual experience. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Iacoboni M (2003) Understanding others: Imitation, language, empathy. In: Hurley S, Chater N (eds) Perspectives on imitation: from cognitive neuroscience to social science. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1890) The principles of psychology. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod M (1994) The representing brain: neural correlates of motor intention and imagery. Behav Brain Sci 17:187–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod M (2001) Neural simulation of action: a unifying mechanism for motor cognition. NeuroImage 14:S103–S109

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1781/1998) Critique of pure reason. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Kawato M (1999) Internal models for motor control and trajectory planning. Curr Opin Neurobiol 9:718–27

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn SM, Sussman A (1994) Roles of imagery in perception: or, there is no such thing as immaculate perception. In: Gazzaniga M (ed) The cognitive neurosciences. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 1035–1042

    Google Scholar 

  • Kunde W, Koch I, Hoffmann J (2004) Anticipated action effects affect the selection, initiation and execution of actions. Q J Exp Psychol A 57(1):87–106

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G (1987) Women, fire, and dangerous things: what categories reveal about the mind. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahon B, Caramazza A (2005) The orchestration of the sensory-motor systems: clues from neuropsychology. Cogn Neuropsychol 22:480–494

    Google Scholar 

  • Mehta B, Schaal S (2002) Forward models in visuomotor control. J Neurophysiol 88:942–953

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Miall RC, Wolpert DM (1996) Forward models for physiological motor control. Neural Netw 9(8):1265–1279

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Middleton FA, Strick PL (2000) Basal ganglia output and cognition: evidence from anatomical, behavioral, and clinical studies. Brain Cogn 42(2):183–200

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan J, Noe A (2001) A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behav Brain Sci 24(5):883–917

    Google Scholar 

  • Pezzulo G, Calvi G (2006a) A schema based model of the praying mantis. In: Nolfi S, et al (eds) From animals to animats 9, Proceedings of the ninth international conference on simulation of adaptive behaviour. vol LNAI 4095. Springer, Berlin, pp 211–223

  • Pezzulo G, Calvi G (2006b) Toward a perceptual symbol system. In: Proceedings of the sixth international conference on epigenetic robotics: modeling cognitive development in robotic systems. Lund University Cognitive Science Studies 118

  • Pezzulo G, Baldassarre G, Butz MV, Castelfranchi C, Hoffmann J (2006) An analysis of the ideomotor principle and tote. In: Butz M, et al (eds) Proceedings of the third workshop on anticipatory behavior in adaptive learning systems (ABiALS 2006)

  • Piaget J (1954) The construction of reality in the child. Ballentine

  • Popper KR (1996) Alles Leben ist Problemlösen. Über Erkenntnis, Geschichte und Politik. R. Piper-Verlag, München

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti G, Arbib MA (1998) Language within our grasp. Trends Neurosci 21(5):188–194

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti G, Fogassi L, Gallese V (2001) Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the understanding and imitation of action. Nat Rev Neurosci 2:661–670

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Roitblat H (1980) Codes and coding processes in pigeon short-term memory. Anim Learn Behav 8:341–351

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenblueth A, Wiener N, Bigelow J (1943) Behavior, purpose and teleology. Philos Sci 10(1):18–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roy D (2005) Semiotic schemas: a framework for grounding language in action and perception. Artif Intell 167(1–2):170–205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloman A, Chappell J (2005) The altricial-precocial spectrum for robots. In: Proceedings of IJCAI

  • Smith BC (1996) On the origin of objects. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor C (1971) What is involved in a genetic psychology? In: Mischel T (ed) Cognitive development and epistemology. Academic, New York, pp 393–416

    Google Scholar 

  • Tolman E (1932) Purposive behavior in animals and men. Appleton-Century-Crofts, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky LS (1978) Mind in society: The development of higher psychological processes. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert DM, Kawato M (1998) Multiple paired forward and inverse models for motor control. Neural Netw 11(7–8):1317–1329

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert DM, Gharamani Z, Jordan M (1995) An internal model for sensorimotor integration. Science 269:1179–1182

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work is supported by the EU-funded project MindRACES: from Reactive to Anticipatory Cognitive Embodied Systems (FP6-511931). Thanks to Joachim Hoffmann for insightful discussions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Giovanni Pezzulo.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pezzulo, G., Castelfranchi, C. The symbol detachment problem. Cogn Process 8, 115–131 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10339-007-0164-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10339-007-0164-0

Keywords

Navigation