Skip to main content
Log in

Replacement in Logic

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We study a range of issues connected with the idea of replacing one formula by another in a fixed (linguistic) context. The replacement core of a consequence relation ⊢ is the relation holding between a set of formulas {A 1, ..., A m , ...} and a formula B when for every context C(·), we have C(A 1), ..., C(A m ), ... ⊢ C(B). Section 1 looks at some differences between which inferences are lost on passing to the replacement cores of the classical and intuitionistic consequence relations. For example, we find that while the inference from A and B to \(A \land B\), sanctioned by both these initial consequence relations, is retained on passage to the replacement core in the classical case, it is lost in the intuitionistic case. Further discussion of these two (and some other) logics occupies Sections 3 and 4. Section 2 looks at the m = 1 case, describing A as replaceable by B according to ⊢ when B is a consequence of A by the replacement core of ⊢, and inquiring as to which choices of ⊢ render this induced replaceability relation symmetric. Section 5 investigates further conceptual refinements— such as a contrast between horizontal and vertical replaceability—suggested by some work of R. B. Angell and R. Harrop (and a comment on the latter by T. J. Smiley) in the 1950s and 1960s. Appendix 1 examines a related aspect of term-for-term replacement in connection with identity in predicate logic. Appendix 2 is a repository for proofs which would otherwise clutter up Section 3.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Ackermann, W. (1950). Widerspruchsfreier Aufbau der Logik I: Typenfreies System ohne tertium non datur. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 15, 33–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Ajtai, M., & Gurevich, Y. (1987). Monotone versus positive. Journal of the Association for Computing Machinery, 34, 1004–1015.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Angell, R. B. (1960). The sentential calculus using rule of inference R e . Journal of Symbolic Logic, 25, 143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Angell, R. B. (1960). Note on a less restricted type of rule of inference. Mind, 69, 253–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Bigelow, J., & Pargetter, R. (1990). Science and necessity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Paperback edition 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Blok, W. J., & Pigozzi, D. (1987). Algebraizable logics. Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, 77, #396.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Bonnay, D., & Westerståhl, D. (2010). Logical consequence inside out. In M. Aloni, H. Bastiaanse, T. de Jager, & K. Schulz (Eds.), Logic, language and meaning: 17th Amsterdam colloquium (LNAI 6042) (pp. 193–202). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  8. Burris, N. S. (1998). Logic for mathematics and computer science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Church, A. (1975). Reviews of Angell [3, 4]. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 40, 602–603.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Czelakowski, J. (1981). Equivalential logics (I). Studia Logica, 40, 227–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Czelakowski, J. (2001). Protoalgebraic logics. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Font, J. M., & Hájek, P. (2002). On Łukasiewicz’s four-valued modal logic. Studia Logica, 70, 157–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Gödel, K. (1986). On the intuitionistic propositional calculus. In S. Feferman, et al. (Eds.), Kurt Gödel—Collected works (Vol. 1, pp. 222–225). New York: Oxford University Press. Orig. publ. 1932.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Gurevich, Y. (1977). Intuitionistic logic with strong negation. Studia Logica, 36, 49–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Harrop, R. (1954). An investigation of the propositional calculus used in a particular system of logic. Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, 50, 495–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Henkin, L. (1977). The logic of equality. American Mathematical Monthly, 84, 597–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Herrmann, B., & Rautenberg, W. (1990). Axiomatization of the De Morgan type rules. Studia Logica, 49, 333–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Hindley, R. (1993) BCK and BCI logics, condensed detachment and the 2-property. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 34, 231–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Humberstone, L. (2000). What Fa says about a. Dialectica, 54, 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Humberstone, L. (2005). Modality. In F. C. Jackson & M. Smith (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary philosophy (pp. 534–614 (20)). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Humberstone, L. (2005). For want of an “and”: A puzzle about non-conservative extension. History and Philosophy of Logic, 26, 229–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Humberstone, L. (2007). Investigations into a left-structural right-substructural sequent calculus. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 16, 141–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Humberstone, L. (2008). Replacing modus ponens with one-premiss rules. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 16, 431–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Humberstone, L. (2010). Smiley’s distinction between rules of inference and rules of proof. In J. Lear, & A. Oliver (Eds.), The force of argument: Essays in honor of timothy smiley (pp.107–126). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Humberstone, L. (2011). On a conservative extension argument of Dana Scott. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 19, 241–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Indrzejczak, A. (2009). Suszko’s contribution to the theory of nonaxiomatic proof systems. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 38, 151–161.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Kabziński, J. (1983) BCI-algebras from the point of view of logic. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 12, 126–129.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Kowalski, T. (2008). Self-implications in BCI. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 49, 295–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Łoś, J., & Suszko, R. (1958). Remarks on sentential logics. Indagationes Mathematics, 20, 177–183.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Łukasiewicz, J. (1970). A system of modal logic. In L. Borkowski (Ed.), Jan Łukasiewicz: Selected works (pp. 352–390). Amsterdam: North-Holland. First appeared in Journal of Computing Systems, 1, 111–149 (1953).

  31. Lyndon, R. C. (1959). An interpolation theorem in the predicate calculus. Pacific Journal of Mathematics, 9, 155–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Makinson, D. (1973). A warning about the choice of primitive operators in modal logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2, 193–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Malinowski, G. (1981). A characterization of strengthenings of a two-valued non-uniform sentential calculus. Reports on Mathematical Logic, 12, 17–33.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Martin, E. P., & Meyer, R. K. (1982). Solution to the PW problem. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 47, 869–887.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Mortensen, C. (1980). Every quotient algebra for C 1 is trivial. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 21, 694–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Paoli, F., Spinks, M., & Veroff, R. (2008). Abelian logic and the logics of pointed lattice-ordered varieties. Logica Universalis, 2, 209–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Porte, J. (1980). Congruences in Lemmon’s S0.5. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 21, 672–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Prior, A. N. (1964). Two additions to positive implication. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 29, 31–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Prucnal, T., & Wroński, A. (1974). An algebraic characterization of the notion of structural completeness. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 3, 30–33.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Raftery, J. G., & van Alten, C. J. (2000). Residuation in commutative ordered monoids with minimal zero. Reports on Mathematical Logic, 34, 23–57. With corrigendum: Reports on Mathematical Logic, 39, 133–135 (2005).

    Google Scholar 

  41. Rautenberg, W. (1986). Applications of weak Kripke semantics to intermediate consequences. Studia Logica, 45, 119–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Rautenberg, W. (1989). A calculus for the common rules of ∧ and ∨. Studia Logica, 48, 531–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Rosser, J. B. (1951). Review of Ackermann [1]. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 16, 72.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Schotch, P. K., & Jennings, R. E. (1975). Modal logic and the theory of modal aggregation. Philosophia, 9, 265–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Scott, D. (1974). Rules and derived rules. In S. Stenlund (Ed.), Logical theory and semantic analysis (pp. 147–161). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  46. Segerberg, K. (1982). Classical propositional operators. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Shoesmith, D. J., & Smiley, T. J. (1978). Multiple-conclusion logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  48. Smiley, T. (1962). The independence of connectives. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 27, 426–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Smiley, T. (1963). Relative necessity. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 28, 113–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Suszko, R. (1971). Identity connective and modality. Studia Logica, 27, 7–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Thomas, I. (1962). The rule of excision in positive implication. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 3, 64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Troelstra, A. S., & Schwichtenberg, H. (1996). Basic proof theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  53. van Benthem, J. (2006). Open problems in logical dynamics. In D. M. Gabbay, S. S. Goncharov, & M. Zakharyaschev (Eds.), Mathematical problems from applied logic I: Logics for the XXIst century (pp. 137–192). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  54. Williamson, T. (2006). Indicative versus subjunctive conditionals, congruential versus non-hyperintensional contexts. Philosophical Issues, 16, 310–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Williamson, T. (2009). Conditionals and actuality. Erkenntnis, 70, 135–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Zeman, J. J. (1968). The semisubstitutivity of strict implication. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 33, 462–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lloyd Humberstone.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Humberstone, L. Replacement in Logic. J Philos Logic 42, 49–89 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-011-9212-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-011-9212-4

Keywords

Navigation