Skip to main content
Log in

On Possible Worlds with Modal Parts

A Semantics for Modal Interaction

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper is predicated on the idea that some modal operators are better understood as quantificational expressions over worlds that determine not only first-order facts but modal facts also. In what follows, we will present a framework in which these two types of facts are brought closer together. Structural features will be located in (or determined by) the worlds themselves. This result will be achieved by decomposing worlds into parts, where some of these parts will have “modal import” in the sense that they will determine structure on other worldly parts. The main upshot of this will be a clearer grasp of the interaction between modal notions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A non-determinable property in this system will be treated like a determinable with only two determinates, the having of the property and the not having.

  2. This notion of extension is perhaps specific to epistemic states.

  3. In symbols: KKϕ.

  4. An alternative formulation is that K(Kpq), where ‘p’ and ‘q’ have very similar truth conditions.

  5. See Williamson [17] for details.

  6. We switched from possible worlds talk to possibility space talk here.

  7. The notion of possibilities being eliminated or left open by an epistemic state is more or less analogous to Lewis’s [11] notion of possibilities being eliminated or left open by the total evidence of an agent.

  8. = ( 1, 2,… 6,) and = ( 1, 2,… 6) are points in the total possibility space.

  9. In order to prove most of the technical results, we must also require μ(m) ∩ m = ∅ and that composite state types be finite subsets of N.

  10. It is important to notice that, according to this general definition, there can be non-atomic modal states. We must then modify our definition of Ω to take this into account. If mM is a composite modal state, then Ω( m ) is defined as the natural extension of Ω( m ) to W. If MM is a set of modal state types, then Ω( M ) is defined as the intersection of all the Ω( m ), for mM.

  11. Note that the determinant state type is a composite state type, not a basic one.

  12. One can think of the determinant, base and support as arities of a certain kind.

  13. We will serve ourselves to a slight generalization of this semantics for modalities. Instead of having only one modality determined by the modal state type m, and defined in terms of Φ( m ), for m m , we will allow a pair of modalities to be determined by m, one defined in terms of Φ( m ) and the other in terms of the converse of Φ( m ). This is a straightforward adaptation of bidirectional frames to possibility spaces (cf. Blackburn et al. [2: 21–22]).

  14. 𝒯 is a tree iff < is an anti-reflexive and transitive relation < on T such that, for all tT, its restriction to {sT : st} is linear. In a tree, there is only one path from right to left but possibly many from left to right.

  15. Zanardo [18] also develops an non moment-history version of Ockhamist semantics.

  16. It should be clear that ≈ t is a subset of the relation ≡ t , where ≡ t is total binary relation on W t . The Priorean semantics are the special case where ≈ t = ≡ t .

  17. R is trichotomous iff, for all x and y, xRy, x = y or yRx.

References

  1. Aumann, R.J. (1976). Agreeing to disagree. Annals of Statistics, 4, 1236–1239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Blackburn, P., de Rijke, M., Venema, Y. (2001). Modal logic, Cambridge tracts in theoretical computer science (Vol. 53). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Burgess, J. (1979). Logic and time. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 44, 556–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Davies, M., & Humberstone, L. (1980). Two notions of necessity. Philosophical Studies, 38, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Fine, K. (2011). An abstract characterization of the deteminate/determinable relation. Philosophical Perspectives, 25(1), 161–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Gabbay, D., & Shehtman, V.B. (1998). Products of modal logics: part 1. Logic Journal of IGPL, 6(1).

  7. Gaifman, H. (1988). A theory of higher order probabilities. In B. Skyrms & W. Harper (Eds.), Causation, chance, and credence. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  8. García-Carpintero, M., & Maciá, J. (Eds.) (2006). Two-dimensional semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Kamp, H. (1979). The logic of historical necessity: part I. Unpublished typescript.

  10. Lewis, D.K. (1973). Counterfactuals. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Lewis, D.K. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Lewis, D.K. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 549–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Prior, A. (1967). Past, present and future. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  14. Segerberg, K. (1973). Two-dimensional modal logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2(1), 77–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In Studies in logical theory (pp. 47–65). American Philosophical Quarterly. Blackwell.

  16. Thomason, R. (1984). Combinations of tense and modality. In D. Gabbay, & F. Guenthner (Eds.), The handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. 3, pp. 135–165). Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  17. Thomason, R., & Gupta, A. (1980). A theory of conditionals in the context of branching time. Philosophical Review, 89(1), 65–90.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Zanardo, A. (1996). Branching-time logic with quantification over branches: the point of view of modal logic. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 6(1), 1–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Neil Kennedy.

Additional information

This paper was made possible by Grant #149410 of the Fonds de recherche du Québec - Société et culture.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kennedy, N. On Possible Worlds with Modal Parts. J Philos Logic 43, 1129–1152 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-013-9311-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-013-9311-5

Keywords

Navigation