Skip to main content
Log in

Can Machines Think? An Old Question Reformulated

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper revisits the often debated question Can machines think? It is argued that the usual identification of machines with the notion of algorithm has been both counter-intuitive and counter-productive. This is based on the fact that the notion of algorithm just requires an algorithm to contain a finite but arbitrary number of rules. It is argued that intuitively people tend to think of an algorithm to have a rather limited number of rules. The paper will further propose a modification of the above mentioned explication of the notion of machines by quantifying the length of an algorithm. Based on that it appears possible to reconcile the opposing views on the topic, which people have been arguing about for more than half a century.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Around the same time other approaches like Church’s λ-calculus (Church 1936) or Post’s production systems (Post 1943) had been developed. Subsequently, however, it had been proven that all these different formalisms are equivalent with respect to the set of functions which they describe.

  2. Input can be simulated by a subprogram which prints the required input onto the tape.

  3. Of course, the exact complexity depends on the considered universal Turing machine U and may be different for a ‘nonstandard’ universal Turing machine.

  4. To add another technicality to the considerations, we may assume that the considered universal Turing machine has less than say 1,000 lines in its Turing table. An example of such a universal Turing machine can be found, e.g., in Minsky (1962). This would result in the fact that the Kolmogorov complexity depends only to a very limited extent on the respectively considered universal Turing machine.

  5. This holds at least for the engineering approach of AI.

  6. that can be accomplished by an intelligent human.

  7. For some particular k and some given universal Turing machine U.

References

  • Abramson, D. (2008). Turing’s responses to two objections. Minds and Machines, 18, 147–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adleman, L. (1979). Time, space and randomness. Technical report, Massachusetts Institute of Technology. MIT/LCS/79/TM-131.

  • Church, A. (1936). An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory. American Journal of Mathematics, 58.

  • Copeland, B. J. (2002). Hypercomputation. Minds and Machines, 12, 461–502.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L., Taddeo, M., & Turilli, M. (2009). Turing’s imitation game: Still an impossible challenge for all machines and for some judges—an evaluation of the 2008 Loebner contest. Minds and Machines, 19, 145–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutter, M. (2005). Universal artificial intelligence: Sequential decisions based on algorithmic probability. Berlin: Springer.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Legg, S., & Hutter, M. (2007). Universal intelligence: A definition of machine intelligence. Minds and Machines, 17(4), 391–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levin, L. A. (1984). Randomness conservation inequalities: information and independence in mathematical theories. Information and Control, 61.

  • Li, M., Vitányi, P. (2008). An introduction to Kolmogorov complexity and its applications. Text and Monographs in Computer Science, 3rd edn. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, J. R. (1961). Minds, machines, and Gödel. Philosophy, 36, 112–117. (rpt. in: Minds and Machines, ed. Alan R. Anderson, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall, 1964).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Minsky, M. (1962). Size and structure of universal Turing machines using tag systems. In: Recursive function theory, proceedings, symposium on pure mathematics, Vol. 5, pp. 229–238. American Mathematical Society.

  • Penrose, R. (1989). The Emperor’s new Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1994). Shadows of the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1996). Beyond the doubting of a shadow. Psyche, 2, 89–129.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2003). Alan Turing and the mathematical objection. Minds and Machines, 13, 23–48.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2007). Computationalism, the Church-Turing thesis, and the Church-Turing fallacy. Synthese, 154, 97–120.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Post E. L. (1943). Formal reduction of the general combinatorial decision problem. American Journal of Mathematics, 65.

  • Sekanina, L. (2007). Evolved computing devices and the implementation problem. Minds and Machines, 17, 311–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O. (1997). Two dogmas of computationalism. Minds and Machines, 7, 321–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O. (2002). Effective computation by humans and machines. Minds and Machines, 12, 221–240.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Solomonoff, R. J. (1964). Complexity-based induction systems: Comparisons and convergence theorems. Information and Control, 7, 1–22 and 224–254.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. M. (1937). On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 2(42), 230–265 and (43) 544–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. M. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 59, 433–460.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Achim Hoffmann.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hoffmann, A. Can Machines Think? An Old Question Reformulated. Minds & Machines 20, 203–212 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-010-9193-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-010-9193-z

Keywords

Navigation