Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Towards a socially constructed and objective concept of mental disorder

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I argue for a new way to understand the integration of facts and values in the concept of mental disorder that has the potential to avoid the flaws of previous hybrid approaches. I import conceptual tools from the account of procedural objectivity defended by Helen Longino to resolve the controversy over the definition of mental disorder. My argument is threefold: I first sketch the history of the debate opposing objectivists and constructivists and focus on the criticisms that led to the emergence of the debate. Second, I offer a reconstruction of the “Natural Function Approach” (NFO) argument to make explicit an unsound assumption underlying this approach. The reconstruction will allow me to show that the NFO’s argument depends on the ideal of value-free science that I will criticize. Then I propose an alternative ideal for psychiatry: social objectivity. I argue that the concept of mental health should be seen as “socially objective” rather than value-free, moving the debate towards the social procedures by which the definition is produced rather than the normative and factual content of its definition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Another way to address the issue of the definition can be called the «ostensible approach» (see Rounsaville et al. 2002, p. 6 for the appellation). This approach has been defended by Lilienfeld and Marino (1995). They argue that we classify mental conditions as mental disorders if they are similar enough to prototypical cases of mental disorders, such as schizophrenia or depression. Finding an operational definition of mental disorder that would encompass all cases of mental disorders is then seen as doomed to fail. However, this approach leaves aside the question of values in the definition of mental disorder, which is the main interest of this paper.

  2. Regarding the presence or absence of value in the definition of mental disorder, note that Wakefield can also be classified as the proponent of what has been called the “hybrid approach”, because he adopts a “two layers approach” to defining mental disorder. He identifies value-laden and a value-free constituents in the definition: harm and dysfunction. However, since both Wakefield and Boorse argue for the existence of a pure value-free notion of dysfunction in the definition of mental disorder, I believe it is legitimate to classify them in the same approach: the natural function objectivist approach (NFO), being part of the naturalist approach about the places and roles of values in the definition of mental disorder. By this, I want to emphasize the opposition between one side that argues for the sole presence of social and cultural values in the definition of mental disorder, the normativists, and the other side for which at least the dysfunction component in the definition of mental disorder is value-free, the NFO.

  3. One could argue that some specifications such as the potentiality of appropriate treatment in Cooper’s account could overcome this criticism. Since there is no potential treatment for lack of humor, but potential treatment for depression, we could demarcate between healthy and disordered states, even if both are socially disvalued. However, it is not clear that the same kind of demarcation can be drawn for every contentious case. For instance, psychological treatments (unfortunately) exist for homosexuality (and some societies consider this condition bad), but it doesn’t mean that homosexuality should be considered as a mental or somatic disorder. Someone could claim that this treatment is non-effective (then not appropriate, as the definition requires), but that doesn’t show that it can’t potentially become effective in the future. Suppose that in a society S, homosexuality is seen as a bad thing to have and that an appropriate and effective “treatment” exists, then in S homosexuality becomes a disorder. The same goes for ugliness: plastic surgery exists, is practiced by doctors and is in most cases efficient, but this doesn’t mean that ugliness should be conceived as a disorder.

  4. An exception here might be another type of constructivism. The neo-Aristotelian approach has defended the existence of objective values that could guide the demarcation between mental health and disorder, based on the idea of vital goals (e.g., Megone 1998a, b, 2000; Nordenfelt 1995). For instance, Megone’s approach is grounded in Aristotle’s account of dysfunction, in which normal functions are processes and states that allow human beings to live as good human beings. A good human being is to be understood as someone who lives her life according to norms of rationality typical of the human species. Normal functions are those that help humans live a fully rational life (Megone 2000). While this account is innovative, it encounters big enough problems trying to look for alternative options. The main limit of this approach is the controversial nature of “a good human life”, and the claim that this conception can be universal (See e.g., Cooper 2017a, p. 280 for this type of criticism. See also Bolton 2000 and Hobbs 1998 for other lines of criticism). As I show later, it might be better to argue that the type of values at play in the definition of mental disorder be intersubjectively and critically examined rather than found in a neo-Aristotelian account.

  5. It should be noted that the distinction between epistemic and non-epistemic values has been challenged, see e.g., Rooney (2017).

  6. More fine-grained distinctions about the meaning of objectivity could be made (like those made by Douglas 2004 or Lloyd 1995). However, for my purposes here, I am more interested in the distinction made by Longino because I believe it relates the debate over the possibility of an «objective» definition of mental disorder as it took place in the philosophy of psychiatry.

  7. See e.g., Jukola (2015) for a more detailed discussion of Longino’s social objectivity and commercial biomedical research in general, and how major funding from the pharmaceutical industry can partly explain the adoption of “the biological psychiatry approach,” according to which mental disorders have to be understood as neurophysiological failures. As Jukola argues, some proposals have been made to address this specific way that commercial interests affect science, such as the enhancement of public funding (Elliott 2011, see also Haque et al. 2014), but this solution lies outside of the social objectivity model as operationalized it in this paper.

References

  • American Psychiatric Association. (1980). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (3rd ed.). Washington, DC.

  • American Psychiatric Association. (1994). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorder. (4th ed.) Washington, DC.

  • Armstrong, T. (2010). Neurodiversity: Discovering the extraordinary gifts of autism, ADHD, dyslexia, and other brain differences. Cambridge: Da Capo Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aucouturier, V., & Demazeux, S. (2013). The concept of “mental disorder”. In H. Carel & R. Cooper (Eds.), Health, illness and disease (pp. 89–106). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayer, R. (1981). Homosexuality and American psychiatry: The politics of diagnosis. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayer, R. (1987). Homosexuality and American psychiatry: The politics of diagnosis. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Betz, G. (2013). In defence of the value free ideal. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 3(2), 207–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biddle, J. (2007). Lessons from the Vioxx debacle: What the privatization of science can teach us about social epistemology. Social Epistemology, 21(1), 21–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biddle, J. (2013). State of the field: Transient underdetermination and values in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44(1), 124–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biddle, J., & Kukla, R. (2017). The geography of epistemic risk. In K. Elliott & T. Richards (Eds.), Exploring inductive risk: Case studies of values in science (pp. 215–237). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bingham, R., & Banner, N. (2014). The definition of mental disorder: Evolving but dysfunctional? Journal of Medical Ethics, 40(8), 537–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blease, C. (2017). Philosophy’s territorialism: Scientists can talk about values too. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 24(3), 231–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolton, D. (2000). Alternatives to disorder. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 7(2), 141–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolton, D. (2008). What is mental disorder? An essay in philosophy, science, and values. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1975). On the distinction between disease and illness. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 5, 49–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1976). What a theory of mental health should be. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 6(1), 61–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44(4), 542–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1997). A rebuttal on health. In J. M. Humber & R. F. Almeder (Eds.), What is disease? (pp. 1–134). Totowa: Humana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (2014). A second rebuttal on health. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 39(6), 683–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boysen, G. A., & Ebersole, A. (2014). Expansion of the concept of mental disorder in the DSM-5. The Journal of Mind and Behavior, 35(4), 225–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boysen, G., Ebersole, A., Casner, R., & Coston, N. (2014). Gendered mental disorders: Masculine and feminine stereotypes about mental disorders and their relation to stigma. The Journal of Social Psychology, 154(6), 546–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boysen, G. A., & Logan, M. (2017). Gender and mental illness stigma: The relative impact of stereotypical masculinity and gender atypicality. Stigma and Health, 2(2), 83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broadbent, A. (2019). Health as a secondary property. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70(2), 609–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Browne, T. K. (2017a). A role for philosophers, sociologists and bioethicists in revising the DSM: A philosophical case conference. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 24(3), 187–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Browne, T. K. (2017b). An ethics review panel for the DSM: A worthwhile challenge. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 24(3), 235–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueter, A. (2010). Social objectivity and the problem of local epistemologies. Analyse & Kritik, 32, 213–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueter, A. (2018). Public epistemic trustworthiness and the integration of patients in psychiatric classification. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01913-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueter, A. (2019a). A multi-dimensional pluralist response to the DSM-controversies. Perspectives on Science, 27(2), 316–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueter, A. (2019b). Social epistemology and psychiatry. In R. Bluhm & S. Tekin (Eds.), Bloomsbury companion to philosophy of psychiatry (pp. 485–503). London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, P. J. (1995). They say you’re crazy: How the world’s most powerful psychiatrists decide who’s normal. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chesler, P. (1989). Women and madness (2nd ed.). New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad, P. (1992). Medicalization and social control. Annual Review of Sociology, 18(1), 209–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2002). Disease. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 33(2), 263–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2005). Classifying madness (Vol. 86). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2007). Psychiatry and philosophy of science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2011). Mental health and disorder. In R. Chadwick, H. Have, & E. M. Meslin (Eds.), The SAGE handbook of health care ethics (pp. 251–260). Los Angeles: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2014). Diagnosing the diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders. London: Karnac Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2015). Must disorders cause harm? The changing stance of the DSM. In S. Demazeux & P. Singy (Eds.), The DSM-5 in perspective (pp. 83–96). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2017a). Health and disease. In J. A. Marcum (Ed.), The Bloomsbury companion to contemporary philosophy of medicine (Vol. 23, pp. 275–296). London: Bloomsbury Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2017b). A modest proposal. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 24(3), 207–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2018). Understanding the DSM-5: Stasis and change. History of Psychiatry, 29(1), 49–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosgrove, L., Bursztajn, H. J., Krimsky, S., Anaya, M., & Walker, J. (2009). Conflicts of interest and disclosure in the American Psychiatric Association’s Clinical Practice Guidelines. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 78(4), 228–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosgrove, L., & Krimsky, S. (2012). A comparison of DSM-IV and DSM-5 panel members’ financial associations with industry: a pernicious problem persists. PLoS Medicine, 9(3), e1001190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosgrove, L., Krimsky, S., Vijayaraghavan, M., & Schneider, L. (2006). Financial ties between DSM-IV panel members and the pharmaceutical industry. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 75(3), 154–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosgrove, L., & Riddle, B. (2004). Gender bias and sex distribution of mental disorders in the DSM-IV-TR. In P. J. Caplan & L. Cosgrove (Eds.), Bias in psychiatric diagnosis (pp. 127–140). Lanham: Jason Aronson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosgrove, L., & Wheeler, E. (2013a). Industry’s colonization of psychiatry: Ethical and practical implications of financial conflicts of interest in the DSM-5. Feminism & Psychology, 23, 93–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosgrove, L., & Wheeler, E. E. (2013b). Drug firms, the codification of diagnostic categories, and bias in clinical guidelines. The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 41(3), 644–653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cranor, C. F. (1990). Some moral issues in risk assessment. Ethics, 101(1), 123–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Melo-Martín, I., & Intemann, K. (2009). How do disclosure policies fail? Let us count the ways. The FASEB Journal, 23(6), 1638–1642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Decker, H. S. (2013). The making of DSM-III: A diagnostic manual’s conquest of American psychiatry. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeVito, S. (2000). On the value-neutrality of the concepts of health and disease: unto the breach again. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 25(5), 539–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. (2004). Epistemic and non-epistemic values in science. In P. Machamer & G. Wolters (Eds.), Science, values, and objectivity (pp. 52–77). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. E. (2003). The moral responsibilities of scientists (tensions between autonomy and responsibility). American Philosophical Quarterly, 40(1), 59–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2004). The irreducible complexity of objectivity. Synthese, 138(3), 453–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2007). Rejecting the ideal of value-free science. In H. Kincaid, J. Dupré, & A. Wylie (Eds.), Value-free science? Ideals and illusions (pp. 120–141). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2009). Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Doust, J., Jean Walker, M., & Rogers, W. A. (2017). Current dilemmas in defining the boundaries of disease. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 42(4), 350–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drescher, J., & Merlino, J. P. (2007). American psychiatry and homosexuality: An oral history. Binghamton, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2007). Fact and value. In H. Kincaid, J. Dupré, & A. Wylie (Eds.), Value-free science? Ideals and illusions (pp. 27–41). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. C. (2008). Scientific judgment and the limits of conflict-of-interest policies. Accountability in Research, 15(1), 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. C. (2011). Is a little pollution good for you? Incorporating societal values in environmental research. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, H. T. (1975). The concepts of health and disease. In H. T. Engelhardt & S. T. Spicker (Eds.), Evaluation and explanation in the biomedical sciences (pp. 125–141). Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Freedman, K. L. (2009). Diversity and the fate of objectivity. Social Epistemology, 23(1), 45–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fulford, K. W., Broome, M., Stanghellini, G., & Thornton, T. (2005). Looking with both eyes open: fact and value in psychiatric diagnosis? World Psychiatry, 4(2), 78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2006). Psychiatric disorders and biological dysfunctions: Some philosophical questions concerning psychiatry, PhD Thesis (unpublished).

  • Goosens, W. K. (1980). Values, health, and medicine. Philosophy of Science, 47(1), 100–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haque, O. S., Lu, A., Wu, D., Cosgrove, L., & Bursztajn, H. J. (2014). Curing financial conflicts of interest in psychiatric professional organizations. In J. Z. Sadler, B. Fulford, & C. W. van Staden (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of psychiatric ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbs, A. (1998). Commentary on” Aristotle’s Function Argument and the Concept of Mental Illness”. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 5(3), 209–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Intemann, K. (2010). 25 years of feminist empiricism and standpoint theory: Where are we now? Hypatia, 25(4), 778–796.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jukola, S. (2015). Longino’s theory of objectivity and commercialized research. In S. Wagenknecht, N. J. Nersessian, & H. Andersen (Eds.), Empirical philosophy of science, studies in applied philosophy, epistemology and rational ethics (Vol. 21, pp. 127–143). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kendler, K. S., Appelbaum, P. S., Bell, C. C., Fulford D Phil, MRC Psych, K. W. M., Ghaemi, S. N., Schaffner, K. F., et al. (2008). Issues for DSM-V: DSM-V should include a conceptual issues work group. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 165(2), 174–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingma, E. (2007). What is it to be healthy? Analysis, 67(2), 128–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingma, E. (2013). Naturalist accounts of mental disorder. In publié par KWM Fulford, M. Davies, R. Gipps, G. Graham, J. Sadler, G. Stanghellini, & T. Thornton (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy and psychiatry (pp. 363–384). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingma, E. (2014). Naturalism about health and disease: adding nuance for progress. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy: A Forum for Bioethics and Philosophy of Medicine., 39(6), 590–608.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirk, S. A., & Kutchins, H. (1992). The selling of DSM: The rhetoric of science in psychiatry. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirmayer, L. J., & Young, A. (1999). Culture and context in the evolutionary concept of mental disorder. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 108(3), 446–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koskinen, I. (2017). Where is the epistemic community? On democratisation of science and social accounts of objectivity. Synthese, 194(12), 4671–4686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kourany, J. A. (2008). Replacing the ideal of value-free science. In D. Howard, J. Kourany, & M. Carrier (Eds.), The challenge of the social and the pressure of practice, science and values revisited (pp. 87–111). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kupfer, D. J., First, M. B., & Regier, D. A. (2002). A research agenda for DSM-V. Washington DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kutchins, H., & Kirk, S. A. (1997). DSM: The psychiatric bible and the creation of mental disorders. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, C. J., & Schunn, C. D. (2011). Social biases and solutions for procedural objectivity. Hypatia, 26(2), 352–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lemert, E. M. (1951). Social pathology: A systematic approach to the theory of sociopathic behavior. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemert, E. M. (1967). Human deviance, social problems, and social control. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lexchin, J., & O’Donovan, O. (2010). Prohibiting or ‘managing’ conflict of interest? A review of policies and procedures in three European drug regulation gencies. Social Science and Medicine, 70, 643–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lilienfeld, S. O., & Marino, L. (1995). Mental disorder as a Roschian concept: A critique of Wakefield’s “harmful dysfunction” analysis. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 104(3), 411–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. A. (1995). Objectivity and the double standard for feminist epistemologies. Synthese, 104(3), 351–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (2002). The fate of knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Loring, M., & Powell, B. (1988). Gender, race, and DSM-III: A study of the objectivity of psychiatric diagnostic behavior. Journal of Health and Social Behavior, 29(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lunbeck, E. (1994). The psychiatric persuasion: Knowledge, gender, and power in modern America. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, N. (2001). Feminist bioethics and psychiatry. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 26(4), 431–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Megone, C. (1998a). Aristotle’s function argument and the concept of mental illness. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 5(3), 187–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • Megone, C. (1998b). Response to the commentaries. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 5(3), 221–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Megone, C. (2000). Mental illness, human function, and values. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 7(1), 45–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moynihan, R. N., Cooke, G. P., Doust, J. A., Bero, L., Hill, S., & Glasziou, P. P. (2013). Expanding disease definitions in guidelines and expert panel ties to industry: A cross-sectional study of common conditions in the United States. PLoS Medicine, 10(8), e1001500. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.1001500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, D. (2015). Concepts of disease and health. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/health-disease/.

  • Nordenfelt, L. Y. (1995). On the nature of health: An action-theoretic approach. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Offman, A., & Kleinplatz, P. J. (2004). Does PMDD belong in the DSM? Challenging the medicalization of women’s bodies. Canadian Journal of Human Sexuality, 13(1), 17–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, J., et al. (2012). The six most essential questions in psychiatric diagnosis: a pluralogue part 1: Conceptual and definitional issues in psychiatric diagnosis. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine, 7(1), 3–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pierre, J. M. (2010). The borders of mental disorder in psychiatry and the DSM: Past, present, and future. Journal of Psychiatric Practice, 16(6), 375–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Porter, D. (2017). Ontological assumptions, a biopsychosocial approach, and patient participation: Moving toward an ethically legitimate science of psychiatric nosology. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 24(3), 223–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potter, N. N. (2001). Key concepts: Feminism. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 8(1), 61–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potter, N. N. (2006). What is manipulative behavior, anyway? Journal of Personality Disorders, 20, 139–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potter, N. N. (2008). The problem with too much anger: A philosophical approach to understanding anger in borderline personality disordered patients. In C. Charland & P. Zachar (Eds.), Fact and value in emotion (pp. 53–86). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Potter, N. N. (2012). Mad, bad, or virtuous? The moral, cultural, and pathologizing features of defiance. Theory & Psychology, 22(1), 23–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potter, N. N. (2014). Oppositional defiant disorder: Cultural factors that influence interpretations of defiant behaviour and their social and scientific consequences. In H. Kincaid & J. A. Sullivan (Eds.), Classifying psychopathology: Mental kinds and natural kinds (pp. 175–194). Cambridge, NE: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pouncey, C., & Merz, J. F. (2017). Browne’s external DSM ethical review panel: That dog won’t hunt. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 24(3), 227–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (2002). The collapse of the fact/value dichotomy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reznek, L. (1987). The nature of disease. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rooney, P. (2017). The borderlands between epistemic and non-epistemic values. In K. C. Elliott & D. Steel (Eds.), Current controversies in values and science (pp. 31–46). New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, P. A. (2002). Values and objectivity in psychiatric nosology. In J. Sadler (Ed.), Descriptions and prescriptions: Values, mental disorders, and the DSMs (pp. 45–55). Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rounsaville, B. J., Alarcón, R. D., Andrews, G., Jackson, J. S., Kendell, R. E., & Kendler, K. (2002). Basic nomenclature issues for DSM-V. In D. J. Kupfer, M. B. First, & D. S. Regier (Eds.), A research agenda for DSM-V (pp. 1–30). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruphy, S. (2006). “Empiricism all the way down”: A defence of the value-neutrality of science in response to Helen Longino’s contextual empiricism. Perspectives on Science, 14(2), 189–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sadler, J. Z. (Ed.). (2002). Descriptions and prescriptions: Values, mental disorders, and the DSMs. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadler, J. Z. (2005). Values and psychiatric diagnosis (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadler, J. Z., & Agich, G. J. (1995). Diseases, functions, values, and psychiatric classification. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 2(3), 219–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarbin, Theodore R. (1967). On the futility of the proposition that some people be labeled “mentally ill”. Journal of Consulting Psychology, 31(5), 447–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheff, T. J. (1966). Users and non-users of a student psychiatric clinic. Journal of Health and Human Behavior, 7, 114–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheff, T. J. (1970). Schizophrenia as ideology. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 1(2), 15–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, P. H. (2007). Defining dysfunction: Natural selection, design, and drawing a line. Philosophy of Science, 74(3), 364–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaw, C., & Proctor, G. (2005). Women at the margins: A critique of the diagnosis of borderline personality disorder. Feminism & Psychology, 15(4), 483–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Showalter, E. (1985). The female malady: Women, madness, and English culture, 1830–1980. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, J. (2007). Beyond naturalism and normativism: Reconceiving the ‘disease’debate. Philosophical Papers, 36(3), 343–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sisti, D., Young, M., & Caplan, A. (2013). Defining mental illnesses: Can values and objectivity get along? BMC Psychiatry, 13(1), 346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2001). Social empiricism. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2009). Standpoint and creativity. Hypatia, 24(4), 226–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spitzer, R. L. (1973). A proposal about homosexuality and the APA nomenclature: Homosexuality as an irregular form of sexual behaviour and sexual orientation disturbance as a psychiatric disorder. American Journal of Psychiatry, 130(11), 1214–1216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spitzer, R. L. (1981). The diagnostic status of homosexuality in DSM-III: A reformulation of the issues. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 138(2), 210–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spitzer, R. L., & Endicott, J. (1978). Medical and mental disorder: Proposed definition and criteria. In R. L. Spitzer & D. F. Klein (Eds.), Critical issues in psychiatric diagnosis (pp. 15–39). New York, NY: Raven Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szasz, T. S. (1960). The myth of mental illness. American Psychologist, 15(2), 113–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szasz, T. S. (1961). The myth of mental illness: Foundations of a theory of personal conduct. New York: Dell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szasz, T. S. (1973). Mental illness as a metaphor. Nature, 242(5396), 305–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ussher, J. M. (1991). Women’s madness: Misogyny or mental illness?. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ussher, J. M. (2011). The madness of women: Myth and experience. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ussher, J. M. (2013). Diagnosing difficult women and pathologising femininity: Gender bias in psychiatric nosology. Feminism & Psychology, 23(1), 63–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varga, S. (2011). Defining mental disorder. Exploring the ‘natural function’ approach. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine, 6(1), 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varga, S. (2015). Naturalism, interpretation, and mental disorder. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C. (1992a). Disorder as harmful dysfunction: A conceptual critique of DSM-III-R’s definition of mental disorder. Psychological Review, 99(2), 232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C. (1992b). The concept of mental disorder: On the boundary between biological facts and social values. American Psychologist, 47(3), 373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C. (1993). Limits of operationalization: A critique of Spitzer and Endicott’s (1978) proposed operational criteria for mental disorder. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 102(1), 160–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C. (1995). Dysfunction as a value-free concept: A reply to Sadler and Agich. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 2(3), 233–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C. (1999). Mental disorder as a black box essentialist concept. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 108(3), 465–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C. (2007). The concept of mental disorder: Diagnostic implications of the harmful dysfunction analysis. World Psychiatry, 6(3), 149–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C., & First, M. B. (2003). Clarifying the distinction between disorder and nondisorder: Confronting the overdiagnosis (False-positives) problem in DSM-V. In K. A. Phillips, M. B. First, & H. A. Pincus (Eds.), Advancing DSM: Dilemmas in psychiatric diagnosis (pp. 23–55). Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilholt, T. (2009). Bias and values in scientific research. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 40, 92–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. A. O. (1985). Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wylie, A. (2015). A plurality of pluralisms: Collaborative practice in archaeology. In F. Padovani, A. Richardson, & J. Tsou (Eds.), Objectivity in science (Vol. 310)., Boston studies in the philosophy and history of science Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Anke Bueter, Luc Faucher, Maël Lemoine and Sophia Rousseau-Mermans for their help with previous versions of this paper, as well as three anonymous reviewers for Synthese for their critique, questions and suggestions. Thanks to Eric Muszynski for linguistic revisions and helpful comments. I would also like to thank audiences of the workshops “Philosophy of Medicine Meets Social Epistemology” (Hanover, Germany) and “Issues in Medical Knowledge” (Cologne, Germany) where I gave earlier versions of this paper. This work was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council (SSHRC) (Grant No. 767-2014-1733).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anne-Marie Gagné-Julien.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gagné-Julien, AM. Towards a socially constructed and objective concept of mental disorder. Synthese 198, 9401–9426 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02647-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02647-7

Keywords

Navigation