Skip to main content
Log in

Searle's Chinese Box: Debunking the Chinese Room Argument

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

John Searle's Chinese room argument is perhaps the most influential andwidely cited argument against artificial intelligence (AI). Understood astargeting AI proper – claims that computers can think or do think– Searle's argument, despite its rhetorical flash, is logically andscientifically a dud. Advertised as effective against AI proper, theargument, in its main outlines, is an ignoratio elenchi. It musterspersuasive force fallaciously by indirection fostered by equivocaldeployment of the phrase "strong AI" and reinforced by equivocation on thephrase "causal powers" (at least) equal to those of brains." On a morecarefully crafted understanding – understood just to targetmetaphysical identification of thought with computation ("Functionalism"or "Computationalism") and not AI proper the argument is still unsound,though more interestingly so. It's unsound in ways difficult for high church– "someday my prince of an AI program will come" – believersin AI to acknowledge without undermining their high church beliefs. The adhominem bite of Searle's argument against the high church persuasions of somany cognitive scientists, I suggest, largely explains the undeserved reputethis really quite disreputable argument enjoys among them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Boden, M. A. (1990), ‘Escaping from the Chinese Room’, in Margaret Boden, ed., The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 89–104. Originally appearad as Chapter 8 of Boden, Computer Models of the Mind, Cambridge University Press: Cambridge (1988).

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1979), ‘Individualism and the mental’, in P. French, T. Uehling, and H. Wettstein, eds., Studies in Metaphysics: Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol. 4, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 73–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carleton, L. (1984), ‘Programs, Language Understanding, and Searle’, Synthese 59, pp. 219–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copi, I. (1986), Introduction to Logic (7th edition), New York: Macmillan Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. and Smith Churchland, P. (1990), ‘Could a Machine Think?’, Scientific American 262, pp. 32–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1980), ‘The Milk of Human Intentionality’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, pp. 425–430.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1985), ‘Machines and the Mental’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 59, pp. 23–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1988), Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, J. A. (1988), ‘TheWrong Stuff: Chinese Rooms and the Nature of Undertanding’, Philosophical Investigations 11, pp. 279–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1990), A Theory of Content and Other Essays, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harnad, S. (199l), ‘Other Bodies, Other Minds: a Machine Incarnation of an Old Philosophical Problem’, Minds and Machines 1, pp. 5–25.

  • Hauser, L. (1993a), Searle's Chinese Box: The Chinese Room Argument and Artificial Intelligence, East Lansing, Michigan: Michigan State University (Doctoral Dissertation).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, L. (1993b), ‘Why Isn't my Pocket Calculator a Thinking Thing?’, Minds and Machines 3, pp. 3–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, L. (1993c), ‘The Sense of “Thinking”’, Minds and Machines 3, pp. 21–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, L. (1993d), ‘Reaping theWhirlwind:Reply to Harnad's “Other Bodies, Other Minds”’, Minds and Machines 3, pp. 219–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, L. (1994a), ‘Acting, Intending, and Artificial Intelligence’, Behavior and Philosophy 22, pp. 22–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, L. (1994b.) ‘Propositional Actitudes: Reply to Gunderson’, Behavior and Philosophy 22, pp. 35–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, L. (1996), “Strong AI” “Weak AI’”, posting to the Usenet Newsgroup Artificial Intelligence Discussions (comp.ai), 10 Feb. 1996.

  • Hayes, P. J. (1982), ‘Introduction’, in P. J. Hayes and M.M. Lucas, eds., Proceedings of the Cognitive Curricula Conference , vol. 2, Rochester, NY: University of Rochester.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodges A., (1983), Alan Turing: the Enigma, New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, D. (1980), ‘Reductionism and Religion’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, pp. 433–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripe, S. (1982), Wittgenstein, Rules, and Private Language, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke (1982), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Wittgenstein, Rules, and Private Languages.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacQueen, K. G. (1990), ‘Not a Trivial Consequence’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13, pp. 193–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984), Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minsky, M. (1996), ‘RE: “Strong AI” “Weak AI”’, posting to the Usenet Newsgroup Artificial Intelligence Discussions (comp.ai), 11 Feb. 1996.

  • Moor, J. H. (1988), ‘The Pseudorealization Fallacy and the Chinese Room Argument’, in J. H. Fetzer, ed., Aspects of Artificial Intelligence, Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 35–53.

  • Myhill, J. (1951), ‘On the Ontological Significance of the LÖwenheim–Skolem Theorem’, in M. White, ed., Academic Freedom, Logic, and Religion, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A. (1979), ‘Physical Symbol Systems’, Lecture at the La Jolla Conference on Cognitive Science.

  • Newell, A. and Simon, H. A. (1963), ‘GPS, a Program That Simulates Human Thought’, in E. Feigenbaum and J. Feldman, eds., Computers and Thought, New York: McGraw-Hill, pp. 279–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975), ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’, in K. Gunderson, ed., Language, Mind, and Knowledge: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science , vol. 7, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1981), Reason, Truth and History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1983), Philosophical Papers vol. 3: Realism and Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. O. (1960), Word and Object, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapaport, W. J. (1988), ‘Syntactic Semantics: Foundations of Computational Natural Language Understanding’, in J. Fetzer, ed., Aspects of Artificial Intelligence, Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer, pp. 81–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapaport, W. J. (1993), ‘Because Mere Calculating isn’t Thinking?’, Minds and Machines 3, pp. 11–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey, G. (1986), ‘Searle's “Chinese Room”’, Philosophical Studies 50, pp. 169–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1980a), ‘Minds, Brains, and Programs’, Behavioral ond Brain Sciences 3, pp. 417–424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1980b), ‘Intrinsic Intentionality’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, 450–456.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. (1980c), ‘Analytic Philosophy and Mental Phenomena’, in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 5, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 405–423.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1982), ‘The Chinese Room Revisited’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5, pp. 345–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1983), Intentionality: an Essay in the Philosophy of Mind, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1984), Minds, Brains, and Science, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1987), ‘Indeterminacy, Empiricism, and the First Person’, Journal of Philosophy LXXXIV, pp. 123–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1988), ‘Minds and Brains Without Programs’, in C. Blakemore and S. Greenfield, eds., Mindwaves, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 209–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1989a), ‘Reply to Jacquette’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research XLIX, pp. 701–708.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1989b), ‘Consciousness, Unconsciousness, and Intentionality’, Philosophical Topics XVII, pp. 193–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1990a) ‘Is the Brain's Mind a Computer Program?’, Scientific American 262, pp. 26–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J. R. (1990b), ‘The Causal Powers of the Brain’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13, p. 164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1990c), ‘Who is Computing with the Brain?’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13, pp. 632–640.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J., R. (1991). ‘Perception and the Satisfactions of Intentionality’, in E. Lepore and R. Van Gulick, eds., John Searle and His Critics, Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell, pp. 181–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R (1992), The Rediscovery of the Mind, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R., J. McCarthy, H. Dreyfus, M. Minsky, and S. Papert (1984), ‘Has Artificial Intelligence Research llluminated Human Thinking?’, Annals of the New York City Academy of Arts and Sciences 426, pp. 138–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharvy, R (1985), ‘It Ain't the Meat it's the Motion’, Inquiry 26, pp. 125–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. (1950), ‘Computing Machinery and Intelligence’, Mind LIX, pp. 433–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiss, T. (1990), ‘Closing the Chinese Room’, Ratio (New Series) III, pp. 165–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilks, Y. (1982), ‘Searle's Straw Man’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5, pp. 344–345.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958), Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hauser, L. Searle's Chinese Box: Debunking the Chinese Room Argument. Minds and Machines 7, 199–226 (1997). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008255830248

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008255830248

Navigation