Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-2lccl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T06:36:15.128Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Near-equational and equational systems of logic for partial functions. I1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

William Craig*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of California, Berkeley, California 94720

Extract

Equational logic for total functions is a remarkable fragment of first-order logic. Rich enough to lend itself to many uses, it is also quite austere. The only predicate symbol is one for a notion of equality, and there are no logical connectives. Proof theory for equational logic therefore is different from proof theory for other logics and, in some respects, more transparent. The question therefore arises to what extent a logic with a similar proof theory can be constructed when expressive power is increased.

The increase mainly studied here allows one both to consider arbitrary partial functions and to express the condition that a function be total. A further increase taken into account is equivalent to a change to universal Horn sentences for partial and for total functions.

Two ways of increasing expressive power will be considered. In both cases, the notion of equality is modified and nonlogical function symbols are interpreted as ranging over partial functions, instead of ranging only over total functions. In one case, the only further change is the addition of symbols that denote logical functions, such as the binary projection function Ae that maps each pair ‹a0, a1› of elements of a set A into the element a0. An addition of this kind results in a language, and also in a system of logic based on this language, which we call equational In the other case, instead of adding a symbol for Ae, one admits those special universal Horn sentences in which the conditions expressed by the antecedent are, in a sense, pure conditions of existence. Languages and systems of logic that result from a change of this kind will be called near-equational. According to whether the number of existence conditions that one may express in antecedents is finite or arbitrary, the resulting language and logic shall be finite or infinitary, respectively. Each of our finite near-equational languages turns out to be equivalent to one of our equational languages, and vice versa.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1989

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

This part contains §§1–3 and the bibliography. Part II, §§4–7, will appear in the next issue of this Journal.

References

REFERENCES

[AN]Andréka, H. and Németi, I., Generalization of the concept of variety and quasivariety to partial algebras through category theory, Dissertationes Mathematicae/Rozprawy Matematyczne, vol. 204 (1983).Google Scholar
[AN8?]Andréka, H. and Németi, I., Corrections of a calculus for equations for partial algebras, Algebra Universalis (to appear).Google Scholar
[ACN]Andréka, H., Craig, W., and Németi, I., A system of logic for partial functions under existence-dependent Kleene equality, this Journal, vol. 53 (1988), pp. 834839.Google Scholar
[Ba]Barendregt, H. P., The lambda calculus, its syntax and semantics, 2nd rev. ed., North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1984.Google Scholar
[Be]Bernays, P., Betrachtungen zum Sequenzen-Kalkul, Contributions to logic and methodology in honor of J. M. Bocheński, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1965, pp. 144.Google Scholar
[Bi]Birkhoff, G., Lattice theory, 3rd new ed., Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, Rhode Island, 1967.Google Scholar
[Bu]Burmeister, P., Partial algebras-survey of a unifying approach towards a two-valued model theory for partial algebras, Algebra Universalis, vol. 15 (1982), pp. 306358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[Bu86]Burmeister, P., A model theoretic oriented approach to partial algebras, Akademie-Verlag, Berlin, 1986.Google Scholar
[BS]Burris, S. and Sankappanavar, H. P., A course in universal algebra, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1981.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[Ev]Evans, T., The word problem for abstract algebras, Journal of the London Mathematical Society, vol. 26 (1951), pp. 6471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[FMMT]Freese, R. S., McKenzie, R. N., McNulty, G. F., and Taylor, W. F., Algebras, lattices, varieties. Vol. 2, Wadsworth & Brooks/ Cole, Monterey, California (to appear).Google Scholar
[Gr]Grätzer, G., Lattice theory. First concepts and distributive lattices, Freeman, San Francisco, California, 1971.Google Scholar
[He]Hertz, P., Über Axiomensysteme für beliebige Satzsystem, Mathematische Annalen, vol. 101 (1929), pp. 457514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[Hoe]Hoehnke, H.-J., Superposition partieller Funktionen, Studien zur Algebra und ihre Anwendungen, Akademie-Verlag, Berlin, 1972, pp. 725.Google Scholar
[Hoe77]Hoehnke, H.-J., On partial algebras, Universal algebra(Esztergom, 1977), Colloquia Mathematica Societatis Jänos Bolyai, vol. 29, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1982, pp. 373412.Google Scholar
[How]Howard, Charles M., An approach to algebraic logic, Ph.D. thesis, University of California, Berkeley, California, 1965.Google Scholar
[J]John, R., A note on implicational subcategories, Contributions to universal algebra (Szeged, 1975), Colloquia Mathematica Societatis Jänos Bolyai, vol. 17, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1977, pp. 213222.Google Scholar
[J78]John, R., Gültigkeitsbegriffe für Gleichungen in partiellen Algebren, Mathematische Zeitschrift, vol. 159 (1978), pp. 2535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[La]Lambert, K., Meinong and the principle of independence, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1982.Google Scholar
[Leb]Leblanc, H., Existence, truth, and provability, State University of New York Press, Albany, New York, 1982.Google Scholar
[ŁS]Łoś, J. and Suszko, R., Remarks on sentential logics, Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen, Proceedings, Series A, vol. 61 ( = Indagationes Mathematicae, vol. 20) (1958), pp. 178183.Google Scholar
[LT]Lindenbaum, A. and Tarski, A., Über die Beschränktheit der Ausdrucksmittel deduktiver Theorien, Ergebnisse eines Mathematischen Kolloquiums, vol. 7 (1936), pp. 1522; revised English translation in A. Tarski, Logic, semantics, metamathematics. Papers from 1923 to 1938, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1956, Chapter XIII, pp. 384–392.Google Scholar
[Ma]Malcev, A. I., Iterative algebras and Post varieties, Algebra i Logika Seminar, vol. 5 (1966), no. 2, pp. 524; English translation in A. I. Malcev, The metamathematics of algebraic systems. Collected papers: 1936–1967, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1971, Chapter XXX, pp. 396–415.Google Scholar
[MMT]McKenzie, R. N., McNulty, G. F., and Taylor, W. F., Algebras, lattices, varieties. Vol. 1, Wadsworth & Brooks/Cole, Monterey, California, 1987.Google Scholar
[Ob]Obtułowicz, A., The logic of categories of partial functions and its applications, Dissertationes Mathematicae/Rozprawy Matematyczne, vol. 241 (1986).Google Scholar
[Ob87]Obtułowicz, A., Algebras of constructions. I: The word problem for partial algebras, Information and Computation, vol. 73 (1987), pp. 129173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[Rob]Robinson, Anthony, Partial functions under Kleene equality: a complete and an incomplete set of rules, this Journal, vol. 54 (1989), pp. 354362.Google Scholar
[Ros]Rosenberg, I. G., Galois theory for partial clones, Universal algebra and lattice theory (proceedings, Puebla, 1982), Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1004, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1983, pp. 253272.Google Scholar
[Ru]Rudak, L., A completeness theorem for weak equational logic, Algebra Universalis, vol. 16 (1983), pp. 331337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[Sch]Schmidt, J., On the definitions of algebraic operations in finitary algebras, Colloquium Mathematicum, vol. 9 (1962), pp. 189197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[Sc67]Scott, D., Existence and description in formal logic, Bertrand Russell, philosopher of the century. Essays in his honor (Schoenman, R., editor), Little, Brown, New York, 1967, pp. 181200.Google Scholar
[Sc79]Scott, D., Identity and existence in intuitionistic logic, Applications of sheaves, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 753, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1979, pp. 660695.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[SŁ]SŁomiński, J., Peano algebras and quasi-algebras, Dissertationes Mathematicae/Rozprawy Matematyczne, vol. 62 (1968).Google Scholar